網路城邦
回本城市首頁 時事論壇
市長:胡卜凱  副市長:
加入本城市推薦本城市加入我的最愛訂閱最新文章
udn城市政治社會政治時事【時事論壇】城市/討論區/
討論區知識和議題 字體:
看回應文章  上一個討論主題 回文章列表 下一個討論主題
政治學 – 開欄文
 瀏覽5,140|回應29推薦2

胡卜凱
等級:8
留言加入好友
文章推薦人 (2)

亓官先生
胡卜凱

相對於社會學和心理學,我對政治學的興趣開始得比較晚。一方面從1415歲開始,我主要想了解的問題在倫理學;另一方面,我和大多數人一樣,性向上急功近利;對政治學的興趣始於軍事學。

大學一年級前後我讀了徐訏先生的《回到個人主義與自由主義》,印象深刻35歲以前,我在聖荷西大學附近舊書攤上,買了常常被其他學者介紹和引用的《君王論》和《政府論》,但大概都只讀了1/41/3。不過,馬克思的政治經濟學批判我倒是讀得非常仔細,此書也構成我對政治的基本理解。當然,之後偶而也會涉獵一些政治學方面的書籍,但為數不多。

2002年以前,除了以上四本經典名著之外,我對政治/政治學的了解,大部分來自新聞報導和報紙/期刊上的政治評論。2001年我退休以後開使在網上漫遊由於在不同論壇上經常和其他網友就政治理論與實際議題進行討論,我不時有「書到用時方恨少」的感慨。於是我開始花較多時間閱讀「政治學」領域的書籍

我對「政治」的「定義以及對「民主政治」的詮釋,都是根據以往30多年對政治實務的觀察,以及這段時間對政治理論的領悟,綜合兩者而形成。

本文於 修改第 2 次
回應 回應給此人 推薦文章 列印 加入我的文摘

引用
引用網址:https://city.udn.com/forum/trackback.jsp?no=2976&aid=7216975
 回應文章 頁/共3頁 回應文章第一頁 回應文章上一頁 回應文章下一頁 回應文章最後一頁
《縱欲與虛無之上:現代情境裡的政治倫理》讀後 - 政治篇
推薦1


胡卜凱
等級:8
留言加入好友

 
文章推薦人 (1)

胡卜凱

書名: 《縱欲與虛無之上:現代情境裡的政治倫理》
作者: 錢永祥
出版者: 聯經
出版時間:民國九十年初版


0.  前言

在《《縱欲與虛無之上:現代情境裡的政治倫理》讀後 - 倫理篇》中,我提到政治哲學和政治學不是我主要的閱讀範圍。但因為我從小對政治很有興趣,幾十年來都是一個熱衷的觀察者,由此累積了一些常識和觀點。這裏就《縱欲與虛無之上》的主要論述(下稱本書) --「自由主義」及相關概念(1),提出我的看法,向錢教授和各位網友請教。

我行文的基本假設請見此文(2) 和本書的《讀後 - 倫理篇》。

1.  
政治論述

首先,我根據史特勞斯和德沃金的說法(Strauss1959Dworkin1985),對政治論述做一個層次和/或層面上的分別:

政治哲學
政治學(政治理論)
政治策略
政治意見(2)
政治文宣(口號、神話、鬼話、或門面話等)

我認為這些不同層次/層面的論述都是意識型態(3),或柏格/拉克曼所說的「主觀現實」(Berger/Luckmann1967)。「主觀現實」的概念強調:人對現實的了解,受到論述者的文化(包括歷史、傳統等)、經驗(包括家庭成員、家庭生活、教育等)、環境(包括地理、氣候、政治、經濟、社會等)、境遇(社會存在,如混飯吃的方式)、及語言各種因素的制約。我把人文科學和社會科學的論述,分成三個類別:「理論」、「虛偽意識」、和「次虛偽意識」。

1)
理論:我用「理論」來指示同時符合下列兩個條件的論述:第一,論述目的或功能在說明現象與現象間的關係(4)。第二,論述有局部或短期的適用度或實用性。也就是說,它具有相當的「客觀」成份(5)
2)
虛偽意識:當一個論述的論述者,沒有自覺到她/他的「論述」和現實有相當大的距離或不了解該論述的實踐將傷害到她/他的利益我把這類「論述」稱為「虛偽意識」(6)。國中生通常稱符合第一個條件的論述為「白癡」或「超白癡」。
3)
次虛偽意識:當論述者明知其「論述」和現實有相當大距離,但仍然公開宣揚它們時,我把這類「論述」稱為「次虛偽意識」或「小虛偽意識」表示它們較「虛偽意識」還要低一個等級(7)。用普通話來說,就是比「虛偽意識」還要「遜」。國中生通常把類似這樣的行為叫做「機車」或「超機車」。

當我們研究一個「論述」時,如果不分辨這些層次、層面、和類別,就比較難掌握它的內容意思和功能。

2. 
政治哲學

集體主義和個人主義是政治哲學中兩個主要的對立主張下面指出試圖將其中任何一個「絕對化」論述的盲點

2.1
集體主義

政治哲學或政治學基礎論企圖解決的問題之一是:

「個人和政府之間,誰有最後的權力?」或

「個人和政府之間,誰居優先地位?」

如果我把這兩個問題改成:

「個人和組織之間,誰有最後的權力?」和「個人和組織之間,誰居優先地位?」

我想99.9999%的人,會認為我是白癡,因為答案非常明顯「個人」先於「組織」。

為什麼「政府」一詞改變了人們對文法句型上類似的兩個問題的觀感?除了「政府」和一般組織有性質上的根本不同以外,另一個主要原因是:因為許多人在「政府」和「國家」兩個概念之間畫上等號而這些人又往往認為國家(或民族、種族、族群)有所謂的「超越性」。我舉兩個例子:

1) 
「共同利益」

「共同利益」或「普遍的善」(9)是亞力斯多德倫理學和政治學論述的關鍵概念。但他的思路有一個盲點,那就是他在「同樣」和「共同」間畫上等號同樣全等於共同」。

我認為這個命題能夠「成立」的前提是以下三個條件至少有一個存在:

資源無限大
利益乙可以替代利益甲(10)
兩方(多方)完全「等同」(11)

但它們存在的機率都不大。也就是說,「共同利益」在一般情況下,只具有一個無實物可指的抽象意義或人定意義(2025/05/260.2-1)-c小節)。也就只能做為參考或建構理論模型的假設。如果以它做為建構理論的基礎,這種理論就不免流於「虛偽意識」。其它以「共同利益」或「普遍的善」為立論基礎的各種「社群主義」和「社會契約論」,也就都有同樣的問題。

亞力斯多德並認為:「國家是自然造成的」(Aristotle1981)。他接著宣稱:「國家在優先順位上,高於家庭或個人」(同上引,1253 - 20)

如果我們把亞氏第一句話當做一種修辭的表達方式,我相信它是可以接受的。但第二句話則在字面上有商榷空間。因為任何人有拒絕繼續「玩生存遊戲」的「選擇」。當一個人選擇自殺或「偕亡」時,「國家」就失去了它的「優先」地位,也就沒有最後或最高的「主控權」。

2) 
社群主義

根據基督教論述:一位全知、全能、全在的上帝創造了人從而,人的目的或功能在侍奉/榮耀這位上帝。如果接受這種說法,個人當然沒有最後或最高的「自主權」。

馬里當的「社群主義」理論就是根據這樣的基督教論述衍生出來(Sweetman1999)。對以基督教教義為基礎的「社群主義」來說,「社群」是從「信眾」或「教區」引申而來的概念,或讓這類理論有現世色彩的代用詞。任何「社群主義」的論述,只要稍做修改,就可以拿來打扮「國家主義」或「集體主義」(8)。例如把「社群」改成「社會」,再把「社會」改成「國家」。

3) 
實際應用

「政府」也好,「國家」也好,民族、種族、族群、或社會也好,實際上往往流於一群自以為是國王的人,披在身上的新衣」(胡卜凱,2002e)。有了這樣的了解,我們才能就事論事的討論政治哲學、政治學、和政治運作。

2.2
個人主義

人因為基因的制約是許多群居生物中的一種。即使因為演化,人有了理性,可以脫離部分基因或生理的制約在現實需要下,一個人如果決定活下去,她/他就「不得不」群居。所以,人需要面對自己必須在「社會」中才能「生活」這個現實。

在「我要活下去」的前提下,「社會」和「國家」的確先於「個人」。此小節請參考此文

3.
自由主義

3.1
自由主義的意義

「山」、「水」這類字,具有自然意義,它們沒有太大被混淆的空間。自由主義的意義(概念)則是人訂定的,因此,在使用它時,如果不先界定清楚,有時會引起誤解或不能達意。《縱欲與虛無之上》的主題之一是「自由主義」它在本書中的用法似乎至少有四種

1)
「美國自由主義的髑髏地」(113)這篇文章中,「自由主義」所指的,大概是美國當代政治運作中,所謂「自由派」人士的理論、策略、或口號(Dworkin1985)
2)
「自由主義的政治性格 -- 殷海光與羅爾斯的對照」(327)和「社會整合和羅爾斯自由主義的政治性格」(271)兩篇文章中,「自由主義」的「用法」,大概是指政治哲學學者,企圖為憲政制度建立理論基礎時,所使用的概念、原則、或信念。這種「自由主義」,或許可稱為「古典自由主義」(Boaz1997)
3)
「自由主義與政治秩序 -- 對《自由中國》經驗的反省」(179)一文中,《自由中國》同仁的「自由主義」,大概只是追求「民主」制度的人士所有的一些信念(或幻想?)(12)
4)
同一篇論文中,第2(《自由主義的政治秩序觀》)所描述的「自由主義」,近於「公民擁有充分自由權論」(Boaz1997)(13)

這四種「自由主義」所指示的思想或人物,在傾向民主政治和反對威權制度上一致,但在其他的政治運作中,則有不同的信念、考量、和政策。不宜概括在一起。例如:

a.
美國當前政治運作中的「自由派」,主張政府介入各種社會問題和議題。以政府的權力來促進社會的公平。例如:重新分配財富來達到社會平等,以公車運送學生來達到學校的種族整合等。「自由派」的這些立場和所導致的政策,是公民自由權主義者所反對的。後者主張政府儘量少管事(14)近於老子的「無為而治」。
b.
一般學者把羅爾斯歸於平等自由主義者,或福利國自由主義者。但在某些激進派的眼中,他又成了保守派或反動派。
c.
台灣的「自由主義」者,多半是空想的知識份子,除了追求或堅持「民主」政治的原則或信念之外,對自由、平等、或正義等概念,缺乏理論基礎。在實務上,大概也和他們的美國同道一般,「連怎麼樣把腳踏車放得四平八穩都不知道」(15)


「自由主義」者多半屬於小資產階級(16)。他們一向利用勞工階級做政治運作或鬥爭的盟友或工具。在取得相當的政治實利,能和皇室或大資產階級討價還價後,就出賣勞工階級。這類過程,在法國歷史中一再上演(17)。中國當代「自由主義」者的行徑,只要看看「清流」的嘴臉或吃相(18),就可略知一、二(19)。民進黨在勞工政策的轉向,也可作如是觀。

此小節請參考此文

3.2
平等

「平等」是一個「人定概念」,人們可以用它來建立各種不同的論述。大家熟知的有:

「立足點」的平等相對於「齊頭式」的平等;
「各取所需」的平等相對於「各取所值」的平等。

生物演化的機制是DNA的分裂和組合,它發生的情況是隨機的。基因的不同,造成個別生物之間的差異。有些跑得快、有些力氣大、有些有翅膀、有些有大腦。生物界無所謂平等,人是生物的一種,也就無所謂天生的或自然的平等。因為體力、智力、性向等的不同,造成工作類別、能力、和階層的不同。這些會轉變成經濟地位和社會階層的不平等。中國人過去有句話說:「人一能之己十之」,但等到一個人「十之而能」後,別人己具備了另外九「能」。所以,努力不是到「平等」之路。

另一方面,因為資源有限,人類社會通常需要追求效率。如果需要追求效率,通常需要分工合作。計畫、協調、執行等不同的任務,需要不同的體力、智力、性向、或經驗等來進行。即使具有同樣教育水準的兩個人,她/他所選擇的工作,通常是由個別的體力、智力、性向、或經驗等來決定。其次,如果需要分工合作,通常就需要有人發號司令。人類社會之所以形成「權力」的概念,資源有限和任務性質的不同,是兩個重要的原因。另一個原因是因為有人要吃大碗(20)。因此,人類社會之所以形成「社會階層」(21),有其生理(基因)和社會活動的基礎。(「三個和尚沒水吃」就是因為沒有「社會階層」所致)。以上論述並不表示我主張社會上的不「平等」是合理的。我只是說:「社會中每個人是平等的」這個假設,並不合現實。如果我們以它來建構理論,這個理論很難有實用價值。如果我們接受「社會是不平等的」這個現實,我們可以試圖減低它造成的痛苦指數。

至於公平、正義等,也是「人定概念」。它們的意義或標準,也就因人而異。對甘迺迪或洛克菲勒家族的成員而言,這世界是非常公平的。陳總統在做律師或立法委員時,也許認為這世界非常不公平。現在他私下一定認為這世界是非常公平的。

3.3
「自由」和「平等」兩個概念的關係

「自由」和「平等」是兩個人定概念。它們之間如果有關係,也是人訂定的或人定義的。如果一個人選擇「自由」做指導原則,他可以用種種說法來申述「自由」的概念涵蓋了「平等」的概念。反之,如果另一個人選擇「平等」做指導原則,她可以用種種說法來申述「平等」的概念涵蓋著「自由」的概念。請參考以下的四種說法。

1)
「自由」是追求自己理想的權利珍惜「自由」的人,會同意每個人追求理想的活動不能受限制。但是資源有限,珍惜「自由」的人,會堅持人人必須具有同樣取得資源的機會或管道(包括個人由教育而來的能力)。因此,「自由」的概念預設或涵蓋了「平等」的概念。
2)
人生來一律「平等」所有人不分出身都應該有同樣的機會和權利。因此,珍惜「平等」的人,會同意人人必須有追求她/他所希求事物的「自由」。因此,「平等」的概念預設或涵蓋著「自由」的概念。
3)
人生的目的(或人的責任)是發揮自己的潛能,來達到她/他可能達到的最高境界。另一方面,不但資源有限,而且「物競天擇、適者生存」是自然定律。所以,接受「人應該發揮自己潛能」和「物競天擇」這兩種說法的人,會同意「自由」和「平等」是兩個對立的概念。也就是說,「自由」是強者道德,它鼓勵人發揮自己的潛能。「平等」則是弱者道德,不論有沒有能力,它要求所有的人都有分一杯羹的權利(尼采的觀點)
4)
「自由」和「平等」兩者之間並沒有邏輯上或任何充分/必要條件的關係。如果鼓吹這兩個概念的人,不把他們的立場,或運作它們的條件說清楚,它們大概是被用來作為馬克思所稱的「意識型態」。也就是說:一種戰鬥口號(現世信念、思想拐杖等);在競選時拿來粉飾自己、欺騙大眾的門面話;或寫論文的話題之類(22)

以上四種說法,都可以加油添醋而成為「理論」。當然也都有邏輯上的缺點。網友們可以選擇自己「習慣」的說法。

最後,我認為邏輯上兩者雖然沒有任何充分/必要條件的關係,在實務上,它們則互為前置條件,請參考此文

3.4
政治秩序

「自由主義與政治秩序 -- 對自由中國經驗的反省」(179)一文的第1(《自由主義的政治秩序觀》),介紹了「政治秩序」的概念。它指:「筆者用『政治過程』一詞,泛指社會尚上的個人、群體、以及各種利益,為了爭取或維持有力的地位,透過各種途徑去進行的運作;這類運作所遵循的規範性的規則,構成了筆者所謂的『政治秩序』」(181)。第4(《自由主義的政治秩序觀》)則介紹了巴博爾、柯瑞克等和「政治秩序」這一概念相關的論述。

首先,以「秩序」來表示「規範性的規則」不是很合「秩序」兩字的一般用法。我沒有讀過巴博爾、柯瑞克的書,但從本書的介紹看來,這個概念的用法,也許譯為「安排」或「體制」比較達意。有了「規則」,依照實況,才有「安排」或「體制」。

如果用較具體的語言,來說明錢教授的「政治過程」,它大概是:「政治活動是為了取得一個大部份社會成員都能接受的資源分配方式」。用普通話來說:「政治是為了讓大部份社會成員不用打破頭,也能混一碗飯吃的活動」。從亞力斯多德到霍布士、洛克、從孔子到王安石、孫中山這些務實的學者或政治家,都很了解這個簡單的道理。如果我的詮釋和錢教授的詮釋相容,那麼世界上沒有「為政治而政治」的政治活動。「大家不必打破頭也有飯吃」這個目的,就是建立政治過程「規範性的規則」的基礎。「不必打破頭」和「混碗飯吃」當然獨立於或先在於政治過程。但這並不表示參與政治的人都會遵守根據它們所建立的「規範性的規則」。因為實際上,有很多人不以混碗飯吃為滿足,她/他還要吃「大碗」。這是為什麼我們在「規範性的規則」外,還需要「安排」或「體制」的原因。如果有道德、法律這些「規範性的規則」就夠了,那警察、法院這類的「安排」或「體制」就多餘了(23)。我們可以拿運動競賽來做比較。以得冠軍為唯一目標的選手,她/他的運作(過程),會和以「公平競爭」為主要目標的選手不同(如吃類固醇、如買通裁判)。以門票收入為主要目標的體能遊戲,和以消遣、娛樂為主要目標的體能遊戲,在建立「規則」的基礎上也有不同,例如美式摔跤。即使棒球、足球、籃球等的規則也一直在變。我們不要忘記,相對於人類有文字記載歷史的四千多年,近代民主政治不過是近兩、三百年才有的「過程」。規則也好、秩序也好、安排也好、它們還在動態變化或辯證進行的階段,是正常現象。


羅爾斯、巴博爾、柯瑞克這些「現代」政治學者,有一個思考上的盲點和職業上的壓力。前者指她/他們企圖以馬克思的模式(或幻想),建立一個「科學」的「政治學」(24)。但是她/他們忘了「科學」的第一個原則是觀察事實(25)。後者指她/他們必須出論文和出書來維持自己的飯碗。美國各學會期刊上的論文,5年以後還被引用的,大概不超過20%。以「政治秩序」為例,巴博爾、柯瑞克兩位的重點在說明「遊戲規則隨著遊戲的進行而改變」。我不敢說三歲小孩都懂這個簡單的「辯證」原理,但每個乖巧一些的六歲小孩大概都嘗試過那需要長篇大論的來論述?

3.5
國族主義和自由主義

從基因學或種族學的觀點來看,在台灣90%的人口中,沒有族群的分別,也就沒有相對於中華人民共和國的國族主義。台灣有的是地區主義或沙文主義(26)

4.
對本書其他概念或觀點的感想

4.1
馬克思主義

馬克思的政治學和經濟學觀點,其實不甚了了。他在思想史上的主要貢獻,在社會學的方法論和理論,我指的是他的唯物史觀和相關的論述。它之所以在過去150年當紅,主要是因為蘇聯將它尊為國學(27),使它成了冷戰時期的顯學。我相信美國有很多批判馬克思主義的學者,大概拿到來自中情局「秘密帳戶」的研究費(28)。美國中情局「秘密帳戶」的開銷,當然也包括300美元一套的西裝或聖誕節禮物之類以「國家安全」之名,揩小老百姓的油。馬克思主義之所以當紅,除了它本身的「價值」外,也因為它是一個很容易混飯吃的工具。另一方面,馬克思的思考主題是解析資本主義的社會問題,只要資本主義存在,總有人會以它為「資源」,拿舊瓶裝新酒,給馬克思主義不同的應用和詮釋,或挾馬克思以自重。在「後蘇聯」階段,「學者」要申請關於馬克思主義的研究費,不會再像50 - 80年代容易。要開研討會,也不會像50 - 80年代那樣容易找到「秘密」贊助者。所以我們可以預見,到了2010年左右,馬克思主義就會像今天的康德哲學或存在主義一樣,雖然能保持思想史中的一席地位和價值,也有它局部的相關性,但不會再是一窩蜂式的研究d課題。這一預測,可從過去10年來,關於馬克思主義論文和書籍數目的趨勢得到驗證。

4.2
學術中立

50 - 60年代,學術中立有兩個涵義:

1)
學術研究屬於理論領域,其結果和現實領域(政治、倫理等)沒有直接關係,或其結果不能直接應用到現實領域。
2)
從事學術研究的人,不宜對現實領域發言,以保持「學術」的超然(或崇高)地位。

這兩個涵義在沙特、馬庫色、和卻姆斯基(或譯杭斯基)等大師的入世行動,以及知識社會學和文化研究盛行後,已不再成立或不再時髦(29)。「學術中立」的概念已失去了它在50 - 60年代的規範性。今天它的意義大致如下。

知識社會學和文化研究兩個領域的研究學者,發現我們的觀點都受到許多因素的制約。用口語來說,就是任何人文或社會科學的「知識」都是偏見。因此,當學者以自己所從事的「學術」研究為基礎,對社會議題發表論述時,要遵守一些遊戲規則:

a.
不能以專家自居。換句話說,學術地位或資歷,對一個人所做的論述,並不具有加分的效果。諾貝爾獎得主在社會議題上的發言,和一般民眾在社會議題上的發言同樣「臭屁」(還記得「清流共治」論嗎?)
b.
要說明自己的基本假設和立場。以供大家檢視她/他論述的「意識型態指數」和她/他的前提/結論之間是否具有相關性和/或一致性(30)

我認為學術研究的目的是解釋現象、解答或解決問題。當我們面對問題(如整個社會「向下沉淪」)時,任何人都可以表示意見。對「問題」的某些構成因素有較全面了解的人,或具有分析能力、或長於邏輯思考的人,更有表達意見的衝動或急迫感。政治活動關係到每個人的利益所以,任何人有權利拱她/他認為「理想」的人選或政策。李清流是人,他當然也有權利拱他認為「理想」的人選或政策。其實,對80%的人來說,「理想」是「對我有利」的代用語。諾貝爾獎得主跟任何人一樣要吃飯、打炮、拉屎。但兩年下來,黑金治國換成白痴當道,台灣社會雖說不上每況愈下,但烏煙瘴氣則依舊如昔。兩年來,李清流卻噤若寒蟬,不復當年高喊「清流共治」時的意氣風發和正義凜然。這就讓人懷疑他當初憂國憂民的嘴臉,是不是找了個化妝師刻意打扮出來的。

4.3
現代與現代性

我在此文此文中,都討論到現代與現代性的議題,此處從略。

5.
建議

5.1
方法論的建議

錢教授博覽群書,本書對所評介的思想或論述,也都講得相當的清楚。我不是歷史中心論者,但我認為,當研究思想史或任何人文及社會科學論述時,研究者要掌握該思想或論述的時、空環境,才有機會切實了解它們的內容或功能(或者說意義、用法等)。其次,概念是研究或論述「現實」的工具。我們沒有必要重新去發明或設計車輪,當然有需要去了解西方學者所開發的,現成的概念或理論。但我們要記住,西方學者所面對或了解的「現實」,是在西方的文化、歷史、社會下建構出來的。我們在使用這些理論或概念時,需要做些檢討、篩選、修改的動作。換句話說,我們要注意西方學者的概念或理論和我們的「現實」之間的相關性問題。以下舉兩個例子,說明我以上的看法以上3.1節中,對自由主義的分析,則是另一個例子。

1)
《美國自由主義的髑髏地》

這篇文章中有下面一段話:「美國自由主義的問題何在?要為1960年代自由派的首鼠猶豫辯解,一個不容忽視的事實是,在當時的政治局面裏,保守派才是自由派更強悍的對手。保守派都提出了更為反動、也相當獲得選民支持的主張和作法。」(115)

首先,我不太了解兩個「更」字的用法。自由派在保守派外,還有另一個強悍的對手?其次,我不太了解「反動」兩個字的用法。如果我是美國選民,我很難認同「『相當獲得選民支持的主張和作法更為反動」這個判斷。第三,自由派在60 - 70年代的美國,還是很有勢力。例如:詹森總統的「大社會」計劃;民主黨在19687284的總統候選人分別是:韓福瑞、麥高文、和孟岱爾。他們都屬於傳統的自由派(197680是卡特);麥高文和(70年代)加州州長布朗,算是自由派中的左翼;甘迺迪當時(70 - 80年代)是參議院民主黨的黨鞭(副領袖);華倫當時仍是最高法院首席大法官。這些細節只是提供大家做個參考。我要講的重點是:

美國在70年代開始,逐漸失去了它50 - 60年代在世界經濟上的獨霸地位。日本、德國挑戰美國在鋼鐵工業、汽車工業、電子工業等的市場佔有率。亞洲四小龍侵蝕美國傳統工業的地盤。當時美國的失業率和通貨膨脹率都在10%左右或以上。國際政治上,伊朗拘留美國人質長達一年多。這些才是自由派的政治策略(社會福利、開放貿易、或以和諧的國際秩序為訴求等),不再吸引選民的原因。另一方面,民主黨的傳統票源是勞工、中下階層、和黑人的聯盟,但60年代開始,勞工及中下階層和黑人的差距拉大,當70年代兩(或三)次經濟不景氣時,三者之間互有經濟利益上的衝突。民主黨的黨綱(政策白皮書),很難繼續維持這一聯盟。容我再重複馬克思的觀察:「社會存在決定意識,不是意識決定存在」。70年代後期,美國選民,所謂的「沉默多數」,開始大量流向採取中間路線或中間偏右政策的(參、眾兩院議員及州長)候選人,主要是荷包使然。

2)
《個人抑共同體?--關於西方憲政思想根源的一些想法》

這篇文章中引了張灝先生的一段話:「發自對人性中或宇宙中與始俱來的種種黑暗勢力的正視和省悟:(152)。然後錢教授似乎同意張灝先生的論述,而有以下的申述:「基督教因為對於人性的幽暗傾向有所警覺,因此而是重視客觀的法律制度,以便對權力施加制度上的防範。」(152)

首先,我不了解「與始俱來」和「黑暗勢力」指的是什麼。就我所知,人「與始俱來」的性質有:肚子餓了要吃、皮膚冷了要蓋、老二翹了要幹等等。這些都可以用身體內部的肌肉、激素、神經信號、和神經信號傳導質的相互作用來解釋。把它們稱為「黑暗」,是在定義「黑暗」,不是把它當形容詞用。

我沒有能力討論「原罪」的說法是否講得通,或「幽暗意識」的概念和「法律」及憲政制度的起源之間,有沒有充分或必要條件的關係。但巴比倫人大概在西元前18 – 20世紀前就有了漢默拉比法典。法家思想在中國思想史也一直有相當重要的地位。這些事實顯示「幽暗意識」的概念和「法律」之間,未必有任何實質關係。我可以接受兩者間有依它起(胡卜凱,2002b)的關係。

我認為從基督教的歷史,如教會的組織成立、教皇和領主、國王間的鬥爭、教皇和主教間的鬥爭、教皇和教皇間的鬥爭等過程;以及教會人員是中世紀唯一的知識份子團體這一因素,也許更能說明何以中世紀關於「法律」或憲政的概念及制度來自教會人員。我們也還要了解教會不只是靈修組織,它也是行政組織和企業組織。因此,它和其他任何類似的組織一樣,有權力鬥爭和因為擁有權力而導致的腐化。(更不要說文藝復興時期,教皇還可以建立世家或門閥)。封建領主權力是槍桿子打出來的。相形之下,教皇和主教只能以「意識型態」來奪權。

5.2
研究方向的建議

學術研究的目的是解釋現象、解答或解決問題。胡適之先生曾建議:「少談點主義,多談點方法」。這是一個有助於解決問題的觀點。例如,「平等」的意義(概念),是人訂定的,很難取得普遍共識而且一不注意,就會流入虛偽意識。我建議「知識份子」不要去探究人訂定的意義。要面對問題,企圖找出它的因果關係,提出解決的方法。這大概是錢教授所講的「問題意識」(ii)。例如:與其講「平等」的源頭,不如制定促進社會穩定的政策,以及建構能夠讓個人發揮潛能的環境。前者如美國以重新分配財富的政策,減少或消除城市內的不安定。後者可以增加人類整體的能量、創造新的資源。政策或環境是否適當,通常可以取得某種程度的公評、驗證、和共識。

我們有我們自己的問題。我建議錢教授找些志同道合,跨研究領域的朋友,挑一、兩個台灣、中國、或華人社會當下比較急迫的問題,共同做系統性的探討,提供一些整體性的解決方案。

後記:

本文發表於20028月。刊出的部落格已經不存在;我過去許多文章常常引用此文。因為這兩個原因,前些日子我把它找了出來。重讀之後,發現我20多年來還真的沒有長進。文字和標點符號略有修正,觀點和意旨未改變;增加之後一些拙作的超連結,刊登於此。 -- 2023

如上所說,我在2023就打算把這篇舊作修改、增補後發表。由於體力、精力、腦力持續階梯式下降,遲遲沒能完成。

由於拙作《實然與應然》提到這篇舊作的姐妹篇,我把它找出來,做了一些修正後發表(該欄2025/05/26)。因為這兩篇文章有些關聯,所以決定把本文也略加整理,重新刊出。考慮到上述體力下降的因素,如果等補齊所有「超連結」,還真不知道會拖到猴年馬月。所以除少數重點已經加上外,先行刊出全文,以後再繼續完成。

實然與應然》一文中提及我在兩個先後不同時間點上的看法,可能有「矛盾。我在增補和修正本文時,並沒有對這個問題做調和/修補的工作。我的觀點以發表時間在後拙作中所呈現者為準。 -- 2025

附註:

1.
「概念是每一門學問的基本成分,名詞或術語,則是表達概念的工具。我們所用的名詞或術語,有沒有把一個概念表達得清楚、明白,直接影響到我們思辨的結果。」(胡卜凱,2002b)
2.
政治學或政治理論(political science)、政治策略(political strategy)、政治意見(political opinion)、神話、鬼話、或門面話(grand narrative)
3.
意識型態在此指其廣義的意思(Mannheim1971)。本文在使用馬克思的意義(指做為鬥爭武器的論述)時,會加上引號來區別(「意識型態」)
4.
因果關係、相關關係、附帶關係、充分條件、必要條件等等。
5.
「客觀」在這裏有兩個層次的意思:第一,根據現實或和現實相容的。第二,和多數人(例如大於75%)相通或有共識的(intersubjective)。第二個意思當然是就實際運作而言。當多數人改變想法後,原來是「客觀」的也就淪為「主觀」的。實際運作(”for all practical purposes”FAPP)
6.
此處的虛偽意識和馬克思的用法略有不同。相對於註5的「客觀」而言,「虛偽意識」可以說有兩個判斷的尺度:第一,和現實不相容的,或無法和其他被接受的知識相容的。第二,和多數人(例如大於75%)的想法或認知無法相通或無法取得共識的。請參考註5中對第二個意思所加的但書。
7.
我用以下的例子來說明意識型態、虛偽意識、和次虛偽意識的分別:
a.
意識型態:如果李登輝前總統說:「我不是中國人」,他可能是受到教育、成長環境、或家庭因素的影響。這可由他自述自己在20(22歲?)前,一直「以為自己是日本人」看出來。至於他是自以為是日本人,還是真的是日本人,可以用DNA比對來鑑定,其實這並不重要。照現代大腦神經學的說法,我們人類的大腦神經網路,在10(7—12)左右就大致定形,也就是說,一個人的思考、言語、和行為模式在這時已大致定形。以後雖然還有改變的空間,但要看當事人是否努力去嘗試改變。上述說法的重點是:人在大約10歲以後,已不可能「洗心革面,重新做人」。(俗話說的:狗改不了吃屎的習慣)。如果李登輝前總統在20(22歲?)前,一直「以為自己是日本人」,我敢打賭,他做夢的時候,有50%左右的時間,是在講日本話。
b.
虛偽意識:當陳不中說:「我不是中國人」時,他可能是受到對國民黨的痛恨、對共產黨的恐懼等心理因素的影響,或大腦曾受到傷害等生理因素的影響。所以,他可能不自知「我不是中國人」這一說法的不實(胡卜凱,2002c)
c.
次虛偽意識:如果林濁水委員說:「我不是中國人」時,他在做明知不實的陳述。林委員伶牙俐齒,而且當你接受他論述的前提時,你很少找到他論述不合邏輯的地方。可見他是有而且用大腦的「知識份子」。他知道他在說些什麼,只是他有把老百姓當白癡的習慣或傾向(胡卜凱,2002d)
8.
柏格/拉克曼從「社會化」的觀點講「主觀現實」,和沈岱爾的「自我定位構成論」近似。(但他們沒有做和「社群主義」相同的結論)。如果有人接受沈岱爾從「自我須由社群關係構成」(297)的前提,推出「社群在優先順位上,高於個人」的結論,她/他沒有理由不接受「社會(或國家)在優先順位上,高於個人」的結論。她/他也沒有理由不接受「時代精神在優先順位上,高於個人」的結論,甚至於「絕對精神在優先順位上,高於個人」的結論。從我的立場來看,「時代精神」和「絕對精神」的概念,都是神秘主義的思考模式(或「典範」)
9.
共同利益、普遍的善(common good)。依上、下文,good可詮釋成「利益」或「善」。錢教授譯為「價值」,此詞雖具有中性,但可能會誤導讀者。
10.
用近代遊戲理論中的術語來說,有「共同」(common)利益的兩方,有「雙贏」的可能和機制。有「同樣」(same)利益的兩方,「零和」的可能性就比較高而且未必能找到「雙贏」的機制。舉個實例:作為民進黨及國民黨的總統候選人,陳總統和連戰先生有「同樣」的目標(或所追求的利益)。兩者的行動之間是「零和」關係。同屬於在野黨的總統候選人,連戰先生和宋楚瑜先生也有「同樣」的目標(或所追求的利益)。但兩者之間可能轉變成「雙贏」關係。因為他們的目標(或利益)有加以替代的可能性。他們只要思考下面的問題,就可能找到合作的契機:「幹在野黨的黨主席比較爽,還是幹副總統或行政院院長比較爽?」如果兩人中有一位,認為幹副總統或行政院院長比較爽,則兩人就可以尋求脫離幹在野黨黨主席的機會和機制。我當然不是說國親合就能贏得2004的大選,至少能讓選情緊繃,說不定苦哈哈們又可以拿些加菜金。
11.
完全等同(numerical identity)。關於identity的翻譯,請參考(胡卜凱,2002b)
12.
如錢教授所描述,《自由中國》的作者群有主張憲政制度的,有主張組織反對黨的。徒法不足以自行,是誰都知道的。英國《大憲章》是貴族硬塞進國王喉嚨中美國沒有獨立戰爭,那來的邦聯或聯邦憲法?法國大革命就不必多談了。在威權制度下,搞反對黨就要玩命(白色恐怖)。台灣民主體制的建立,有三個重要的原因:
a.
台灣獨立的「意識型態」,激勵部份年青人和市民去衝鋒陷陣。
b. 70
年代經濟發展後,反對黨或異議人士有財團撐腰或包養。
c. 70
年代經濟發展後,執政黨不再全面控制飯碗,也就不再能(像以前那樣)獨裁專斷。尤其在社會的穩定度上,它必須受財團及中產階級的節制。
上述bc兩個過程,正在中國進行。只是「民主」、「自由」的「意識型態」,不太能騙人去玩命。
13.
如此來了解「公民擁有充分自由權論」(Libertarianism)較適合。錢教授將此概念譯為「放任自由主義」,待商榷。
14.
美國的ACLU(American Civil Liberty Union)以維護個人權利為主旨。此團體在大多數社會議題上,和自由派及黑權派(NAACPNational Association for the Advancement of Colored People)採取聯合陣線。但在個人權利上,此團體偶而會和保守派同一陣線。我記得的有「反向歧視」(reverse discrimination)官司。
15.
美國隔離主義者華勒士(Wallace, G.)的名言:”They (the liberals) don’t know how to park a bicycle straight.”
16.
小資產階級(petit bourgeois)。此詞的意思不是指小規模、小格局、或小資本額的資本家(bourgeois),它主要指附庸於資本家來混飯吃的各種階層(市民階層)。尤其指文革時紅衛兵所說的「走資派的走狗」,或我常批判的「文化圍事」和「幫閒文人」。
17.
最顯著的兩次:1848的二月革命(Kranzberg1959Duveau1967) 1871的巴黎公社(中共中央馬、恩、列、斯著作編譯局,1971)
18.
例如:殷賠款。高鐵八字還沒一撇,我們納稅人就要先賠個一億(還是四億?),她還跩得跟個二、五、八萬一樣,動不動要開記者會。真的是什麼的什麼嘛!?我本來以為:「什麼都要,就是不要臉。什麼都吃,就是不吃虧。」是形容街頭混混。現在看來,形容當前的「清流」,好像更活神活現,入骨三分。這是因為「現代」的道德情境,還是因為「後現代」的語言情境?。
19.
我無意厚誣賢者。如果《自由中國》的班底當權後,他們的作為會強過今天的民進黨,我會大吃一驚。記不記得那首「... 設若當時身便死,日後聲名有誰知?」的詩(大意如此)
20.
陳總統認為在野黨敗選後,還要吃大碗是件荒謬的想法,我完全同意他的判斷。但身為總統,講這種話,不免有缺少理性或沒什麼教養之譏。他言外之意,似乎只有身居廟堂者才夠格吃大碗。照春秋的筆法,以後我會稱陳總統為陳大碗。
21.
社會階層(social stratum)
22.
例如「台獨」。在30 – 50年前,可能有其現實意義,至少可以做為反對國民黨的「戰鬥口號」。等到李前總統上任後,「台獨」已沒有現實環境。它成了部分知識份子為自己生命找「意義」的虛偽意識。對政客而言,純粹是騙人混飯吃的次虛偽意識。相對於中華人民共和國而言,中華民國已是主權獨立的國家。如果有人相信把國名改了,中華人民共和國就不會再宣稱台灣是中國的一部分,我建議她/他去做個大腦斷層掃瞄(fMRI)
23.
如果一個人選擇了生命以外的價值,或其神經系統不很穩定(人不一定永遠或時時是理性的),她/他可能拒絕繼續「玩」生存遊戲。她/他也可能更激情一些,決定玩個玉石俱焚的遊戲。中國古人「時日曷喪,予與汝偕亡!」的宣示、日本神風特攻隊指揮官和隊員的意識、賓拉登911特攻隊隊員的典範 ,都是掌權者不得不遵守某些「政治安排」(錢教授的「政治秩序」)的原因。這個現實及(掌權者)對它們的考量,也獨立於或先在於政治過程。
24.
羅爾斯的 ”comprehensive doctrine” 指的是 ”metaphysical doctrines”  ”speculative doctrines”;他的 ”political conception” 指的是 ”scientific conception” (Rawls1996)
25.
羅爾斯《正義論》的基本假設之一是「人進入社會時是自由而平等的」(Rawls, 1971)。依本文3.2節,我認為他對「不平等」的客觀現實,沒有什麼概念,或他高居象牙塔內,無視於這個客觀現實。
26.
地區主義(provincialism),沙文主義(chauvinism)
27.
歷史上儒家、佛教、道教,都曾享受過同樣的禮遇。
28.
相當於蔡兩國的兩國論。
29.
這和邏輯實證論及心理學中的行為主義(做為學說及方法論)先後失去它們的「顯學」地位,也有關係。
30.
我在American Psychology上一篇論文中看到這個說法。一時查不出原作者不敢掠美,附記於此。

參考書籍和文章:

– Aristotle, 1981, The Basic Works, McKeon, R.
編,馬陵出版社有限公司,台北,1129-1253
– Berger, P. L./Luckmann, T. 1967, “The Social Construction of Reality
A Treatise in the Sociology of Knowledge”, Anchor Books, New York。第3章。
– Boaz, D. 1997, “Libertarianism, A Primer”, The Free Press, New York
– Duveau, G. 1967, Carter, A., (
)譯,“1848: The Making of a Revolution”, Random House, New York
– Dworkin, R. 1985, “A Matter of Principle” Harvard University Press, Cambridge, Massachusetts
115
– Kranzberg, M. ed., 1959, “1848: A Turning Point?”, D. C. Heath and Company, Boston
1 – 23
– Rawls, J. 1971, “A Theory of Justice”, Harvard University Press, Cambridge, Massachusetts
– Rawls, J. 1996, “Political Liberalism”, Columbia University Press, New York

– Strauss, L. 1959, “What Is Political Philosophy? And Other Studies”, The University of Chicago Press, Chicago 1
– Sweetman, B.
1999, The Failure of Modernism, American Maritain Association, Mishawaka, Indiana10 – 12
– Wolff, K. H.
編,1971, “From Karl Mannheim”, Oxford University Press, New York116 – 131
中共中央馬克思、恩格斯、列寧、斯大林著作編譯局編,1971,《論巴黎公社》,人民出版社,北京。
胡卜凱,2002a,《「縱欲與虛無之上:現代情境裡的政治倫理」讀後 -- 倫理篇》,刊於知識和社會廣場,知識區,8月,2002
胡卜凱,2002b,《評《哲學辭典》的中譯本兼論意思和翻譯》,刊於知識和社會廣場,知識區,4月,2002
胡卜凱,2002c,《解構批判陳師孟秘書長對國外媒體的談話》,刊於知識和社會廣場,知識區,6月,2002
胡卜凱,2002d,《判斷模式》,刊於知識和社會廣場,社會區,4月,2002
胡卜凱,2002e,《發刊詞我的論述架構》,第4節。刊於知識和社會廣場,社會區,4月,2002
胡卜凱,2002f,《評《另類哲學:現代社會的後現代化 - 兼論現代性和後現代》,刊於知識和社會廣場,知識區,4月,2002

本文於 修改第 5 次
回應 回應給此人 推薦文章 列印 加入我的文摘
引用網址:https://city.udn.com/forum/trackback.jsp?no=2976&aid=7253312
「美國理想」的三位奠基者 -- Robert Curry
推薦2


胡卜凱
等級:8
留言加入好友

 
文章推薦人 (2)

亓官先生
胡卜凱

The 3 Pillars of the American Idea

Robert Curry, 05/07/25

Unalienable rights and self-evident truths are 
the two core ideas of the American founding.  

Expand the number of core ideas under consideration to three and you get unalienable rights, self-evident truths, and free market economics.

You could call them the three pillars of the American Idea.

These three pillars are the direct gifts to America of three great thinkers of the Scottish Enlightenment: Francis Hutcheson, Adam Smith, and Thomas Reid.

Their thinking — known today as “common sense realism” — took America by storm at precisely the right time to shape America fundamentally.

Francis Hutcheson

Francis Hutcheson: “Our rights are either alienable or unalienable …”                   

A revolution in thinking about our rights preceded the American Revolution. In the words of George Washington, America’s founding took place during a time “when the rights of mankind were better understood and more clearly defined than at any former period.” Hutcheson’s analysis of our rights showed the way.

The meaning of Hutcheson’s distinction was sharp and clear in the founders’ time but to understand it today you and I must first be clear about the meaning of “alienable.” Here is its complete definition in my dictionary: “adj. Law. Capable of being transferred to the ownership of another.” Your right to your car is an alienable right; because your car is your property, you can sell your car or give it away — but our rights to our lives and our liberty are unalienable, that is, not property, not capable of being transferred to the ownership of another.

Hutcheson was challenging John Locke’s account of our rights — and in so doing he helped ignite the American Revolution. Locke, you see, had 
defined our rights in terms of property. Locke: “Man … hath by nature a power … to preserve his property — that is, his life, liberty and estate.” According to Hutcheson and the founders, our rights to our lives and our liberty are not property; those rights are unalienable, inherent, essential, and not transferrable.

Hutcheson’s distinction provided the intellectual foundation for two of the greatest achievements in world history, Adam Smith’s “The Wealth of Nations” and the Declaration of Independence. Adam Smith’s focus was our alienable rights; the American founders focused on our unalienable rights.

The Declaration and “Wealth” both entered the world they were to transform in the same year, 1776.

1776 marks the economic and political boundary between the world in which you and I live and all that had gone before.

Adam Smith

Francis Hutcheson mentored Adam Smith. Upon Hutcheson’s death, Smith was appointed to the prestigious professorship at the University of Glasgow Hutcheson had held.  

Smith’s epoch-making “Inquiry into the Nature and Causes of the Wealth of Nations” is the foundation of free market economics. Hutcheson’s analysis of our rights set the direction Smith took. In “Wealth” Smith famously demonstrated that the division of labor is the source of the wealth of nations. In one of the most frequently quoted passages from “Wealth,” Smith makes clear the source in human nature of the all-important division of labor: “This division of labour … is the necessary … consequence of a certain propensity in human nature … ; the propensity to truck, barter, and exchange one thing for another.” The division of labor depends on the right to exchange (alienate) our property and labor. We can “truck, barter, and exchange” because our right to our property is, as Hutcheson had shown, “naturally alienable.”

The social order that resulted from the new thinking of the Scottish and the American Enlightenments was a far cry from the world that assigned supremacy to hereditary monarchs and hereditary aristocrats. The great economist Ludwig von Misses described that new social order like this: It “assigned supremacy to the common man. In his capacity as a consumer, the ‘regular fellow’ was called upon to determine ultimately what should be produced, in what quantity, and of what quality, by whom, how, and where; in his capacity as a voter, he was sovereign in directing the nation’s policies.”

Thomas Reid

When Jefferson wrote “We hold these truths to be self-evident …” he was relying on the thinking of Thomas Reid.

Reid’s “An Inquiry Into the Human Mind on the Principles of Common Sense” was published in 1764, the same year he was awarded the prestigious professorship formerly occupied by Francis Hutcheson and Adam Smith.

As I write in my book “Reclaiming Common Sense”: “Reid’s philosophical purpose was to provide a foundation for morality and for knowledge. He argued that there is an endowment of human nature that makes both morality and knowledge possible, and he called it common sense … With it we are able to make rational judgments and moral judgments. Common sense is the human attribute that makes it possible for us to be rational creatures and moral agents.  

Reid’s fundamental insight was that our ability to make sense of our experience presupposes certain first principles. Because these principles are implicit in our conduct and our thought, they cannot be proved; there are no other truths from which they can be derived. However, to deny or even to doubt any of them is to involve ourselves in absurdity. Consequently, the principles of common sense have the special authority of first principles: we cannot operate without them.”

The Progressives

From their beginning, the purpose of the Progressives has been the step-by-step — that is, the progressive — undoing of the America of the founders. Their relentless campaign has done tremendous damage. If you and I are to do our part in helping to restore America, we need to go into action armed with a clear understanding of the American Idea. That is why I wrote the two common sense books listed below.


Robert Curry is the author of "
Common Sense Nation: Unlocking the Forgotten Power of the American Idea” and “Reclaiming Common Sense: Finding Truth in a Post-Truth World.” Both are from Encounter Books. His articles and reviews have appeared in American Greatness, the American Thinker, the Claremont Review of Books, and The Federalist.

本文於 修改第 1 次
回應 回應給此人 推薦文章 列印 加入我的文摘
引用網址:https://city.udn.com/forum/trackback.jsp?no=2976&aid=7251774
真共和與假民主 - J. Hankins
推薦1


胡卜凱
等級:8
留言加入好友

 
文章推薦人 (1)

胡卜凱

這篇文章是本欄上一篇的簡略版。這兩篇評論的主旨和本欄2024/10/12以及2024/10/04兩篇貼文相近;對民主制度、共和制度、與美國憲法這三個議題有興趣的朋友,可以把它們合起來看。


Real Republics and Fake Democracies


James Hankins, 09/24/24

Americans have forgotten what the Founders knew about popular government.

In an 
essay recently published in The Free Press, the political commentator Martin Gurri made a nicely arch response to the fashionable hand-wringing about supposed threats to “our democracy.”  

I come with good news. We can’t lose our democracy because we never had one. Our system is called “representative government.” It enjoys brief spasms of democratic involvement—elections, trials by jury—but by and large it glories in being densely and opaquely mediated, and many of its operations are patently undemocraticappointed judges, for example, or the Electoral College. This is a feature, not a bug, of the system. By making sure the right hand of power seldom knows what the left hand is doing, the Framers sought to prevent various flavors of tyranny—including, in James Madison’s words, “an unjust combination of the majority.”

I suppose it was to avoid the appearance of partisanship that Gurri called our political regime “representative government” rather than using the name the Founders used, that is, a republic. This was no doubt a prudent choice of words on his part. So shallow is knowledge of history among our politicians, journalists, and the political nation in general that most would struggle to describe the difference between a republic and a ham sandwich. Heedless of capitalization, they would inevitably associate it with the name of one of our political parties, whose structure is no more republican than the Democratic Party’s organs are democratic. Or they might think of the Staatsname of other current republics like the Democratic Republic of North Korea, or the Islamic Republic of Iran. These associations would also be unenlightening. So “representative government” was no doubt Gurri’s best choice, but it is far from adequate as a description of how the Founders intended the country to govern itself. 

(
略去)

So what understandings of the term “republic” might they have gleaned from their reading?

First of all they would be aware, like Gurri, that a republic is not a democracy. (This is not as obvious as it seems: (
以下略去)

When the Romans conquered the Mediterranean in the second century BC, the historian Polybius explained the growth of their power largely in terms of their (unwritten) constitution, which he recognized as a form of mixed regime. (
以下略去) According to Cicero, Rome’s basic constitutional principles had been laid down by one of the early kings, Servius Tullius. Servius had established the bedrock principle that political power should be proportionate to a man’s income and his contribution to Rome’s military power. Poorer citizens could participate in assemblies but decision-making power was kept in the hands of the most influential citizens. The censors, a magistracy responsible (among other things) for deciding which citizens could belong to the Senate, judged them fit for membership not only on the basis of their moral rectitude, but also on their income. A man without sufficient income to support himself and his family comfortably without engaging in trade or a paid profession was ineligible

Post-classical Athenians, by contrast, continued to call their city-state a democracy even after all the real power came to be exercised behind the scenes by wealthy oligarchs. The great authority on Hellenistic Greece, Peter Green, once wittily remarked that Athenians came to see democracy as a privilege best restricted to the upper classes. Modern parallels spring to mind. The Romans for their part were not in the least embarrassed about the preponderant power of the wealthy in their system. It was a feature, not a bug. But in Rome, the possession of wealth and preponderant power imposed upon the great the responsibility to put themselves and their treasure at the service of the republic. It was assumed that the wealthy would also be the best educated, the most likely to have experience in civil and military affairs, and, as persons of long residence in Rome, the most loyal and public-spirited

If we began again to use the correct historical term for our regime—a republic—we might be able at least to have an honest discussion about who holds power in the American system.

In the middle republic (third and second centuries BC), the principle of merit was added to the Servian constitution: distinguished service to the state was also to be a source of dignitas or merited status. Thus “new men” like Cicero could be taken into the ruling elite on the basis of outstanding abilities and contributions to the republic’s welfare, the salus reipublicae. To prevent the powerful from oppressing the common people a new magistracy was invented, the tribunate, consisting of ten tribunes of the plebs. The existence of this magistracy led to the emergence of populist politics at the end of the second century BC, but Rome never became a democracy. Roman populism ultimately brought Julius Caesar and Augustus to power, over the opposition of the Senate. Rome’s populists were almost always led by nobles who were more devoted to acquiring power for themselves than serving the interests of the common people.

Cicero in his dialogue On the Commonwealth (54–51 BC) praised the old republic for favoring the best men or “optimates,” observing “the principle which ought always to be adhered to in the commonwealth, that the greatest number should not have the greatest power” (ne plurimum valeant plurimi). Rome should never be a democracy; that would be too dangerous for ordered liberty, which was guaranteed by law, not popular power

In a democracy, Cicero believed, sensible public deliberation was impossible. In one of his speeches, Cicero mocked Greek democracies for their foolish practice of herding large numbers of ordinary citizens into amphitheaters and allowing them to shout at each other. The Romans, more sensibly, conducted deliberation in the Senate, among educated men with experience of government. The Senate proposed legislation and the people in their assemblies had the right to vote on the Senate’s proposals, up or down. This practice, that the wise should deliberate and propose, the people approve, was the normal procedure used by most European republics in the centuries before the founding of our American republic. It was recommended, among others, by James Harrington, a seventeenth-century British authority on republics widely read in America.

By establishing a House of Representatives to conduct its own deliberation and to propose all legislation involving taxation (a principle now apparently forgotten in Washington, DC), the Founders were attempting to rebalance the republican tradition they inherited in a popular direction, so that the interests of the wealthy could never prevail over those of the people. Nevertheless, they continued to uphold the view that the presumably wiser and better-educated men in the Senate—Jefferson’s “natural aristocracy”—should prevail in matters of foreign policy and the oversight of the other branches of government. The aristocratic element was also, originally, meant to prevail in the choice of the president, although the Electoral College was soon corrupted by party politics, at which point it lost its deliberative and most of its decision-making power. 

But were history’s only democracies to be found in classical Greece? No. When Mr. Gibbon’s history began to be read in the early republic, Americans were given access to another concept of democracy, different from that associated with classical Athens, one that might be called honorary democracy or, less politely, fake democracy. This concept might remind us of the way the term is used by certain of our contemporaries. 

Gibbon famously regarded the second-century AD, the period between the reigns of the emperors Domitian and Commodus, as “the period in the history of the world, during which the condition of the human race was most happy and prosperous.” The text upon which the great historian hung this judgment (to which, as an upholder of constitutional monarchy, he was predisposed) was an oration entitled An Encomium of Rome (ca. 154–55), written by Aelius Aristides. 

Aristides, the most prominent Greek intellectual of his day, heaped praise on Rome as the greatest empire the world had ever known. It managed to combine unquestioned authority regulated by law with a free citizenry, and its government was not handed over to foreign princes but was administered by fair and disinterested citizen-officials, capable of ruling and being ruled in turn, as in the best days of classical Greece. For Aristides, the Roman empire was more like a city-state on a vast scale than a traditional despotism. Yet its courts of appeal, administered by Roman governors, were an improvement on city-state justice, and they treated everyone equally, no matter what their status. This was an achievement unprecedented in human history, and a great proof of Rome’s genius for government. Virtuous rule had made the empire flourish as no human government had ever done before. By widely extending citizen rights, the empire vastly increased the pool of talent upon which it could draw. 

Aristides could think of no greater praise than to say that the Roman empire was like a democracy over all the earth, under a single best magistrate and bringer of cosmic order. The Roman system, he wrote, is the final state of mankind: “no other way of life is left”—it was the end of history, as it were. No longer does any city wish to revolt from it and to rule itself, and the Romans have made even the memory of war fade by doing away permanently with local struggles for preeminence. The whole world has become a garden with gleaming cities enjoying a perpetual festival of blessings from the emperor and the gods.

This, of course, is flattery under a mask of high-flown rhetoric, decorated with concepts from political philosophy. It didn’t matter that Aristides’s use of the word “democracy”—and he was by no means the only imperial subject who used the word in this sense—matched no known democratic regime in history and had nothing to do with political power in the hands of the people. It was just a word that had positive connotations in Greek; it would sound nice to his listeners and flatter them. Aristides was a professional orator-entertainer who went about the Greek world giving speeches before audiences educated to appreciate the fine art of eloquence. In this instance, Aristides was speaking before the imperial court, and he knew what to say to win their approval

As far as I know, the founding generation never discussed Aristides’ faux democracy. They were serious men who understood the history of political regimes. But perhaps the time to revive Aristides’ concept has now come. Modern politicos who talk glibly of “our democracy” might be asked to explain to the rest of us just what they think democracy is. Is it just a nice-sounding word used to flatter themselves and their political allies, or do they support putting real power in the hands of popular assemblies on the basis of equality? If neither of those alternatives seems palatable, perhaps they might avail themselves of the correct adjective to describe our constitution: republican.

Martin Gurri is right: we are not a democracy. We are a republic, and that is no bad thing. Republics come in several flavors, aristocratic, popular, and mixed. Not all of them are militaristic and dominated by warlords and the wealthy, as the late Roman republic was. In late medieval and early modern times, most republics preferred trade and industry to making war. Even so, some of these commercial republics lasted a very long time, like Venice, which endured for 1,100 years, or Lucca, which lasted for almost 650 years. (Both were crushed by Napoleon.) If modern advocates for “our democracy” fancy themselves lovers of the people, they might appreciate the fact that our republic at its founding was already weighted towards the popular more than previous early modern republics had been. The Seventeenth Amendment to the Constitution made it still more so. If we began again to use the correct historical term for our regime we might be able at least to have an honest discussion about who holds power in the American system, and whether they deserve to do so, instead of playing make-believe with terms that conceal more than they reveal.


James Hankins is a professor of History at Harvard University and a Senior Writer at Law & Liberty. His most recent books are Virtue Politics: Soulcraft and Statecraft in Renaissance Italy and Political Meritocracy in Renaissance Italy.


本文於 修改第 2 次
回應 回應給此人 推薦文章 列印 加入我的文摘
引用網址:https://city.udn.com/forum/trackback.jsp?no=2976&aid=7241398
共和制和做為倫理準則的民主制 -- James Hankins
推薦1


胡卜凱
等級:8
留言加入好友

 
文章推薦人 (1)

胡卜凱

韓金斯教授這篇演講文長了一些(1),雖然一處有內在衝突,另一處似乎近於「認知障礙」;但是總體而言,還算有料。它至少能幫助我們了解所謂「民主制度」的缺點。

另一方面,該文也讓一些開口閉口「西方民主」的人士了解:西方人(至少某些西方學者)自己非常了解「西方民主」有那些所謂的缺點;不像此處某些「政治學者」只會拿「西方民主」一詞當「稻草人」,但是對「西方民主」到底有什麼缺點,卻說不出個所以然。

我會盡量找時間提出拙見,略做討論。

套用一個流行詞(請參見此欄開欄文的附註8),我開個玩笑

那些替中共當局擦脂抹粉的「援嘴」們,如果多讀過幾本書,就不會拿「西方民主」說嘴直接把當下中國政權稱之為「有中國特色的共和制」就更夠力了。

附註:

1. 
韓金斯教授正文中提及他的另一篇文章。該文只有此演講一半字數而且內容大致相同,我會刪節重複同時不是重點部份後刊出。不想讀長篇大論的網友,可以稍等一會兒。

索引:

contrive
:謀劃,策劃,設計
dignitarian thinking
:人格尊嚴論
eo ipso
「僅以此而論」
Federalist Papers, The:聯邦論者說帖
ineradicable
:無法根除的;根深蒂固的
magistrates, Greek:古希臘的行政/司法長官;有資格出任者(貴族、地主、…),經考核後以抽籤方式選出請見超連結
magistrate, Roman:古羅馬官職,請見超連結
Marshall
, John:曾任聯邦最高法院首席大法官
parlous condition
:危險狀況,破落狀況
plebs
:平民,老百姓
salus reipublicae:此處:國家利益,國家前途國家安全
sui iuris:獨立自主
tribunatetribune為古羅馬官職,10tribune構成一個tribunate
Whig:英國政黨(1678 -- 1859)


Republics and the Ethical Ideal of Democracy

Both sides accuse the other of being a threat to democracy. But what does that really mean?

James Hankins, 11/08/24

Editor’s note: This is an edited version of a talk given to the John Marshall Program at Boston College on November 4, 2024.

Let me begin by thanking David DiPasquale for the kind invitation to cross the Charles River and address the John Marshall Program (JMP) here at Boston College and Dallas Terry for helping with the arrangements. When we settled on the date I was working with the professional/academic part of my brain and somehow tuned out the fact that the lecture would take place on the day before the election. The staff of JMP had read an essay I wrote for Law & Liberty about the historical uses of the terms “republic” and “democracy.” They asked me to speak on that subject, but relate it to the timelier theme of elections. I agreed, stipulating that I didn’t want to make a partisan speech but give a historical reflection. However, now that the moment has come to put my ideas into words, I’m not finding it easy to evade the charge of partisanship. We are experiencing a moment of particularly strong passion in our already passionate political life, being literally on the eve of what people are saying is the most important election of our lifetimes. (Let me reassure the younger people in the room that this has been said of every election in my lifetime of nearly seven decades.)

My problem is not just trying to speak on a historical subject at a moment when my audience will be hypersensitive to the partisan implications of my remarks. Election season is a moment when civic-minded people are focused on the present and the future. To bring up the past, especially the remote past I’m going to talk about, appears as an annoying distraction from our most important concerns as a nation. For me personally, it’s also a challenge to speak about history in a moment when the shallowness of Americans’ historical knowledge, and the consequent poverty of our public discourse, have become blindingly obvious. Simple-minded traditionalists like myself have the idea that before elections we should be engaging in some kind of democratic deliberation, discussing the merits of the candidate’s policy proposals, for example. Instead, public discourse has degenerated into an ignorant exercise in name-calling. One side calls the other fascist, the other side calls their opponents communist.

Both claims are hysterical and historically illiterate, and the fact that they are taken seriously at all by anyone is a condemnation of American civic education as well as the absence of deliberation in our public life. Most serious democratic thinkers, from the fifth century BC sophist Protagoras onwards, have believed that participation in the public life of a democracy via deliberation was itself an educational experience for all citizens, and one necessary to the flourishing of democracy. Instead, public deliberation is being led by people who throw around terms of whose meaning they are invincibly ignorant, terms like “republican” and “democratic.” To my mind, it’s like going to an academic conference on biology organized and conducted by people who don’t understand the meaning of the terms botany, zoology, micro-organism, or cell structure.

A disturbing feature of the present moment in our public life is that both sides are accusing the other of being a threat to democracy. People who hold that the events of January 6, 2020, can be plausibly described as the worst insurrection since the Civil War identify the Republican candidate as the chief source of this threat. The wealthiest man in the world shouts back through his megaphone on “X” that the real threat to democracy comes from people who accuse the Republican nominee of endangering democracy. Both parties in the US now take the position that “it’s only democracy when we win.”

No wonder that the latest Georgetown Institute of Politics and Public Service Battleground Civility Poll shows that an alarming number of Americans across party lines believe that the democratic system of government is under threat, although for very different reasons. The poll, conducted by a consortium of Republican and Democratic pollsters, found that 81 percent of respondents agreed with the statement that democracy in America is currently under threat, and 72 percent agreed with that statement strongly. Americans disagree about the source of the threat, however. The forces in America identified as very serious threats to democracy include MAGA Republicans (49 percent, 34 percent extremely serious), major news organizations (47 percent, 24 percent extremely serious), and social media (43 percent, 23 percent extremely serious).

Americans have an almost religious belief that we are a democracy and that democracy is precious to us. On the right, it is said that our personal freedoms depend on democracy, while the left emphasizes that our goodness as a people is threatened by a breakdown in democracy. Everybody has an opinion about this subject, myself included. But a much smaller number seem to have a clear understanding of what democracy is.

Many people, especially foreigners, seem surprised to learn that the US Constitution outlines a form of government that is 
not democratic, but republican. Many Americans have only a vague conceptions of what a republic is. I remember a student—and a Harvard history major!—writing on an exam I gave some years ago that “republic is just an old name for democracy.” In fact, the thinkers who most shaped the US Constitution, John Adams and James Madison, had a horror of the democratic form of government, which they understood from their reading of history to be a proven failure, leading inevitably and quickly to violence, anarchy, and ultimately tyranny. As John Adams wrote in a letter to John Taylor in 1814, “Democracy never lasts long. It soon wastes, exhausts and murders itself. There never was a democracy yet that did not commit suicide.” Even Jefferson, the Founder most confident in the power of the people to govern themselves, thought direct democracy could only be exercised at the local level, and that the principle of self-government would have to be diluted by the device of representation—a republican device—if it were to operate over large areas. Late in life, Jefferson admitted in a letter to William Charles Jarvis (1820) that the American system of a government, consisting as it did of three distinct and independent branches, would not be able to resist judicial oligarchies abusing their powers on partisan impulses unless the people were to step in to prevent that outcome, using their “wholesome discretion.” But they would lack such discretion absent a serious program of civic education, which in that period, before the founding of the public school system in the 1840s, did not exist.

Of course, democracy is not only a form of government, that is, a particular kind of regime or constitution. A democratic regime, as it was understood in antiquity, is like the one used in Athens in the fifth century BC: a form of government, in other words, in which the people govern themselves via councils and assemblies, random selection of magistrates by lot, and juries consisting of hundreds of jurors to prevent bribery and the undue influence of the wealthy on the judicial process. Democracy as it exists in America is better understood, not as a regime, but as an ethical ideal, one that has grown and developed since the Reformation into a way of life and thought built around three concepts: popular sovereignty, personal autonomy, and equality. This characterization of democracy and its fundamental concepts come from what I believe is the best book ever written on the history of democracy as an ethical ideal, namely my colleague James Kloppenberg’s book 
Towards Democracy: The Struggle for Self-Rule in European and American Thought (Oxford 2016). As Kloppenberg notes, democracy as an ethical ideal is unthinkable without the influence of Christianity, particularly Protestant Christianity.

So for the balance of this talk, I aim, first, to explain why the United States Constitution does not outline a democratic regime but a republic, and why the Founders thought a republican regime could channel the popular will without suffering from the bad design of the democratic regimes they knew from history. Second, I will discuss democracy as an ethical ideal and way of life, and argue that the aspirations of Americans to be a democratic society, which emerged strongly after the American Revolution, are failing to be realized. I will leave it up to you to decide for yourselves which party or parties in America are most responsible for that failure.

First, let me put a bit more meat on the bones of my claim that the American system of government is republican (lowercase R!), not democratic (lowercase D!). The reason why the Founders did not want a democratic system of government is that, unlike modern Americans, they knew something about Western history and particularly British history. Anyone who has read The Federalist Papers or the private correspondence of the Founders will be aware of just how deep their knowledge was. John Adams was already exciting Americans in 1774 with the thought that their generation could play the role of the ancient Greek legislators Lycurgus and Solon, or the Roman king Servius Tullius, who established Rome’s Servian constitution. In 1776 he wrote in a famous letter known as Thoughts on Government.

You and I, my dear Friend, have been sent into life, at a time when the greatest law-givers of antiquity would have wished to have lived. How few of the human race have ever enjoyed an opportunity of making an election of government more than of air, soil, or climate, for themselves or their children. When, before the present epoch, had three millions of people full power and a fair opportunity to form and establish the wisest and happiest government that human wisdom can contrive?

The Founders were bookish people, and they turned for inspiration as much to history as to political theorists such as Aristotle, Locke, Algernon Sidney, and Montesquieu. Benjamin Franklin’s Library Company of Philadelphia, founded in 1731, which became effectively the Library of Congress during that assembly’s long residence in the city, was well-stocked with histories. The shelves of John Adams’ library, the largest in colonial America, were also loaded with works of history. His 
writings, like those of Jefferson and Madison, teem with references to the republics of past times: to the ancient Romans above all, but also to the medieval Italian republics, to the Venetian, Swiss, and Dutch republics, and above all, to the English Commonwealth of the seventeenth century. (Note that the word “commonwealth” is just an English translation of the Latin respublica).

Human beings have an ineradicable inclination to evil as well as to good, which is why we need the constraints of a republican regime.

Some of the Founders read Latin, Greek, and French as well as English. They read Thucydides (often in 
Hobbes’ translation), Livy, Sallust, Cicero, and Tacitus; they read Plutarch’s Lives of the Noble Greeks and Romans in Sir Thomas North’s translation; they read Polybius in the translation of James Hampton (in whose pages they could learn about the federal republics of ancient Greece); they read Edward Mortley Montagu’s Reflections on the Rise and Fall of Ancient Republicsof the Italians, they read Leonardo Bruni’s History of the Florentine People, Guicciardini’s History of Italyand Machiavelli’s History of Florence; they read John Jacob Mascou’s History of the Ancient Germans; they read David Hume’s six-volume History of England and Obadiah Hulme’s Historical Essay on the English Constitution. As soon as each volume of Edward Gibbon’s Decline and Fall of the Roman Empire left the presses, between 1775 and 1788, copies flew across the Atlantic and were eagerly consumed by Americans. Americans had good reason to be interested in the collapse of states in those years, when the new Confederation in North America was being torn apart by its weak central institutions.

So what understandings of the term “republic” might they have gleaned from their reading? First of all, they would be aware that a republic is not a democracy. The Founders knew what a democracy was and had no interest in giving America a democratic constitution. They knew their history. The historical experience of classical Athens was taken by nearly all the historians the Founders knew to prove that a democratic constitution was doomed to failure.

Already in the fourth century BC, it was widely believed by Greek thinkers that both pure democracy (Athens) and pure oligarchy (Sparta) were failed forms of government. The great political theorists of the fourth century BC—Plato, Aristotle, Isocrates, and Xenophon—had all proposed various fixes for the defects of democracy. The most influential of these was Aristotle’s “mixedregime, where elements of democracy and oligarchy were balanced against each other to produce stability. Later, Polybius and other writers in the Aristotelian tradition added a monarchical principle for added stability. Aristotle called his mixed regime politeia.

When Aristotle’s Politics was translated into Latin around 1436/37 by the Florentine historian Leonardo Bruni, politeia became respublicaBruni’s translation was the most popular Latin version for centuries. The 
1597 Geneva edition was in John Adams’ library. (Adams also possessed the 1776 edition of the Politics in the English translation of William Ellis, first printed in 1597, where the constitution named politeia was translated, unhelpfully, as “state.”)

When the Romans conquered the Mediterranean in the second century BC, the historian Polybius explained the growth of their power largely in terms of their (unwritten) constitution, which he recognized as a form of mixed regime. The Romans were proud of their republic even in the dark decades of civil war during the first century BC, blaming Rome’s
condition on the moral defects of powerful warlords rather than on any weaknesses in her constitution. According to Cicero, Rome’s basic constitutional principles had been laid down by one of the early kings, Servius Tullius. Servius had established the bedrock principle that political power should be proportionate to a man’s income and his contribution to Rome’s military power. Poorer citizens could participate in assemblies but decision-making power was kept in the hands of the most influential citizens. The censors, a magistracy responsible (among other things) for deciding which citizens could belong to the Senate, judged them fit for membership not only on the basis of their moral rectitude, but also on their income. A man without sufficient income to support himself and his family comfortably without engaging in trade or a paid profession was ineligible.

Post-classical Athenians, by contrast, continued to call their city-state a democracy even after all the real power came to be exercised behind the scenes by wealthy oligarchs. As the great authority on Hellenistic Greece, Peter Green, once wittily remarked, Athenians came to see democracy as a privilege best restricted to the upper classes. Modern parallels spring to mind. The Romans for their part were not in the least embarrassed about the preponderant power of the wealthy in their system. It was a feature, not a bug. But in Rome, the possession of wealth and preponderant power imposed upon the great the responsibility to put themselves and their treasure at the service of the republic. It was assumed that the wealthy would also be the best educated, the most likely to have experience in civil and military affairs, and, as persons of long residence in Rome, the most loyal and public-spirited.

In the middle republic (third to second centuries BC), the principle of merit was added to the Servian constitution: distinguished service to the state was also to be a source of dignitas or merited status. Thus, “new men” like Cicero could be taken into the ruling elite on the basis of outstanding abilities and contributions to the republic’s welfare, the salus reipublicae. To prevent the powerful from oppressing the common people, a new magistracy was invented, the tribunate, consisting of ten tribunes of the plebs. The existence of this magistracy led to the emergence of populist politics at the end of the second century BC, but Rome never became a democracy. Roman populism ultimately brought Julius Caesar and Augustus to power, over the opposition of the Senate. Rome’s populists were almost always led by nobles who were more devoted to acquiring power for themselves than serving the interests of the common people. 

Cicero, in his dialogue On the Commonwealth (54/51 BC), praised the old republic for favoring the best men or “optimates,” observing “the principle which ought always to be adhered to in the commonwealth, that the greatest number should not have the greatest power” (ne plurimum valeant plurimi). Rome should never be a democracy; that would be too dangerous for ordered liberty, which was guaranteed by law, not popular power.

In a democracy, Cicero believed, sensible public deliberation was impossible. In one of his speeches, Cicero mocked Greek democracies for their foolish practice of herding large numbers of ordinary citizens into amphitheaters and allowing them to shout at each other. The Romans, more sensibly, conducted deliberation in the Senate, among educated men with experience of government. The Senate proposed legislation and the people in their assemblies had the right to vote on the Senate’s proposals, up or down. This practice, that the wise should deliberate and propose, the people approve, was the normal procedure used by most European republics in the centuries before the founding of our American republic. It was recommended by many of the Whig writers—among them The Commonwealth of Oceana by James Harrington—that were widely read in America.

By establishing a House of Representatives to conduct its own deliberation and to propose all legislation involving taxation (a principle now apparently forgotten in Washington, DC), the Founders were attempting to rebalance the republican tradition they inherited in a popular direction, so that the interests of the wealthy could never prevail over those of the people. Nevertheless, they continued to uphold the view that the presumably wiser and better-educated men in the Senate—Jefferson’s “natural aristocracy”—should prevail in matters of foreign policy and in the oversight of the other branches of government. The aristocratic element was also, originally, meant to prevail in the choice of the president, through the Electoral College. The Electoral College was supposed to deliberate about the election results and exercise its discretion, but it very quickly, within a decade of the Constitution’s adoption, was corrupted by party politics. At this point, it lost its deliberative and decision-making power.

All that being said, most of the Founders were much more optimistic than the tradition they inherited about the possibility that ordinary citizens could engage in democratic deliberation. What this shows, I believe—and here I am again following Jim Kloppenberg as well as Gordon Wood’s classic work, The Radicalism of the American Revolution (1992)—is that the founding generation and the generations that followed were imbued with the democratic spirit. I mean here the ethical ideal of democracy, as distinct from the political regime. As an ethical ideal, democracy will always be aspirational. Like other ethical ideals, the frailty of human nature means that we will always fall short in our efforts to realize it. Human beings have an ineradicable inclination to evil as well as to good, which is why we need the constraints of a republican regime.

As analyzed by Kloppenberg, the democratic ideal has three main elements: popular sovereignty, individual autonomy, and equalityPopular sovereignty means that the ultimate authority in the state is the people, and that the form of government, whether constitutional monarchy, aristocratic republic, or popular republic, should reflect its will. Members of this John Madison Program will recognize this as Rousseau’s view in The Social Contract, who posited that the sovereign will of the people could be invested in a regime at the moment, historical or notional, when the social contract was formed. After that moment of authorization, the regime established by the contract did not need to seek continuous and regular authorization from the people for its subsequent acts. In the democratic republics that emerged in the nineteenth century, however—modeled to a large extent on the American republic—the popular will had to be expressed continuously through representatives, duly constrained by law and the enumerated powers given to the legislature by the Constitution. Thus, in the American republic, popular sovereignty implies both participation—being open to citizen participation at all levels and in all branches of government—and representation, the authorization of persons who can then represent the will of citizens in the legislature. As the democratic spirit has spread, any barriers to political participation based on race, sex, or property qualifications have been torn down. At the same time, it is widely recognized that popular sovereignty needs constitutional limits to protect individual rights, the common good, and civil peace and stability.

If people do not have confidence that elections are honest and that the courts are non-political, then there can be no democracy.

The gradual removal of barriers to participation has come from the second element identified by Kloppenberg as part of the ethical ideal of democracy: individual autonomy. This means self-rule, being sui iuris as the Romans would say, not being treated or acting as subject to another, but free to choose ends for oneself. In America and Europe, the impetus behind the modern commitment to autonomy came most powerfully from the struggle against slavery and unfree labor. Autonomy combines both positive and negative freedom, the freedom to rule oneself and specific freedoms from constraints imposed by the public power—civil rights, in other words. Autonomy means that all adult citizens should have the capacity to shape their own lives, within the standards set by law, tradition, and custom. All citizens should also be able to participate on an equal basis in shaping those standards, and revising them when necessary. Liberal pluralism is a valuable thing in a country as diverse as ours, but ideally, it should be based on explicit democratic authorization, not imposed by the courts. This is especially the case when advocates of pluralism seek to change settled ways of life, above all those affecting the family and religion. When judges impose pluralism (as Jefferson noted in the letter of 1816 referred to earlier), the people are likely to become estranged from the legal elites who take it upon themselves to dictate social norms.

This brings us to the third element in the democratic ethic: equality. Equality means, minimally, equality of political rights and equality before the law. These were ancient ideals, associated, respectively, with Greece and Rome. In addition, Aristotle recognized that great inequality of incomes was destabilizing and counseled, as a maxim of practical wisdom, as distinct from a principle of justice, that legislators should act to prevent too much inequality in a state.

Modern ideals of equality descend from the idea of innate human equality, a principle first enunciated by the Greek church father Gregory of Nyssa in the fourth century AD. He based the principle of human equality on the individual possession of reason, on being formed in the image and likeness of God, and on the New Testament injunction to treat others, even the poorest and weakest of human beings, as though they were Christ. The republican political tradition was
impregnated with these notions via radical Protestantism in the sixteenth and seventeenth centuries. The modern democratic ethic represents a secularization of these ideas. The weightiest defender of human dignity in its secularized form was Immanuel Kant, whose moral philosophy has been a major source of much later dignitarian thinking.

It is not the exclusive role of governments, of course, to support the democratic ethical ideal; like any other set of ethical beliefs, they need all the sources of reinforcement they can get, including parental teaching, civic education, religious institutions, professional norms, and community standards. Nevertheless, if we want our republic to have a democratic spirit, we need to recognize the ethical preconditions of a democratic way of life, and governments must do what they can to support those norms, or at least not get in their way. Allowing elections to take place is a necessary condition, but hardly a sufficient one.

For the sake of discussion, let me give a short list of three things I believe governments must do to foster the ethical ideal of democracy—what we might also call the democratic way of life or the democratic spirit. There are other preconditions of democratic civil life, but these seem to be the most pressing at the moment.

First, in order to support healthy forms of pluralism and autonomy, democratic states need to foster a particular kind of sociability. They must be committed to allowing fundamental differences between and among the people to persist, including religious differences. Safeguards should exist, at least in the form of peer pressure or common norms, to prevent political parties from demonizing each other. Single political parties should not be allowed to monopolize the public square in which support may be sought from the people. They should also not be allowed to monopolize public education. The government needs to foster a commitment to tolerance. It cannot allow itself to be taken over by utopian fanatics determined to impose their beliefs on their fellow citizens. Governments and public institutions need to encourage a spirit of live and let live, a spirit of reciprocity, and not try to impose a fixed unitary conception of the good life. They need to support a kind of sociability, in short, which allows people of very different beliefs to live and work together with an attitude of mutual respect. This, to me, is far more important to democracy than preserving what is called “diversity” by departments of Human Resources, diversity based only on arbitrary definitions of group identity.

This sort of sociability is much harder to maintain around election time, of course, but I submit that it has been some time, well over two decades, since the spirit of democratic sociability has prevailed in the councils of our government.

Secondly, states must also promote genuine democratic deliberation, and not only among elected representatives in constitutional assemblies. They must also, as much as possible, include the people as a whole in democratic deliberation, promote rational persuasion, and prevent the use of force or fraud in determining the outcomes of political choices. They should be wary of declaring 
states of emergency, as these are historically the antechamber to tyranny. As an example of what should not be done, I would mention the health dictatorships established during the Covid panic. These curtailed our liberties in the most dramatic fashion, and we the people had little to say about it. Democracy almost completely disappeared at just the moment when the state had assumed unprecedented dictatorial power over us. Most of the time these dictatorships were legal in the sense of operating under legislative authority, but that authority was originally designed to last for short periods, not for many months and years. Not allowing proper democratic deliberation in legislatures by the people’s representative about issues that affected everyone’s lives and livelihoods has done much to undermine the idea that our republic is an expression of the will of the people. It caused the hypertrophy of conspiratorial thinking, always a sign of a lack of transparency or the use of deceit in decision-making.

Finally, for the democratic spirit to flourish, governments have to foster an ethic of impartiality among those who are the umpires of democratic deliberation, namely, those who run the electoral system and the courts. The law cannot be politicized or weaponized by one party against another. If people do not have confidence that elections are honest and that the courts are non-political, then there can be no democracy. This principle of impartiality of course is an ethical derivative of the Roman republican conception of the rule of law, a civil law derived from natural law and standing above politics. It is apparently difficult for many people to understand that they cannot oppose persons they take to be demagogues by corrupting the legal system. This only makes the law itself into a demagogue. It should be a primary goal of public education to teach young citizens what the rule of law means, its history, and its successes and failures. This means the young need to be taught Western history, beginning with Roman history.

The ancient Romans saw clearly the need for an impartial and non-partisan legal system. Cicero’s solution to the problems of demagoguery and warlordism in his time was to limit popular self-rule through the rule of law and to prevent political abuse of the law by placing its interpretation in the hands of the wise, a relatively new class of legal experts known as jurisconsults. Roman civil law, which had begun to coalesce as a system of rules for settling court cases in the second century BC, had by Cicero’s time assumed the character of an autonomous source of right, set above social and political competition, to which appeal might be made by all Roman citizens on a basis of equality. In a famous speech, In Defense of Aulus Caecina, Cicero maintained that it was this autonomy of law, its superiority to politics, that made it the “incorruptible guarantor” of civil rights. It created “the bonds of social welfare and life” and had therefore to be “uniform among all and identical for everyone.”

The strong separation of legal processes—in principle at least—from the corruptions of politics became a bedrock principle of Western legal thought. It was reformulated and strengthened in the eighteenth century as the principle of an independent judiciary. For the Romans, the separation of law from politics was what made a man free: it protected him and his property from more powerful figures in the state and their political projects. As Cicero put it, using a dramatic paradox, “the magistrates are ministers of the law, the judges are its interpreters, and we are thus all slaves to the law so that we can be free.” Roman citizens were subject to the law, not to persons; and if they became subject to persons, they were eo ipso slaves or dependents, not sui iuris, directly under law. For this system to work, lawyers had to see themselves as representatives of the law, not of political parties, demagogues, warlords, or any particular interest. It was their solemn obligation and sacred duty to uphold the law and justice, and to put its integrity before any private interest. The requirement that a judge should be impartial and never align himself with a political party, as this group will know, was a bedrock principle of our first Chief Justice of the Supreme Court, John Marshall.

I submit that in all these respects, America is failing to uphold the ethical ideal of democracy, and we are actually falling away from that ideal, becoming less democratic, rather than simply failing to make progress. What are the causes of this deplorable situation and what should be done about it I leave open to discussion.


James Hankins is a professor of History at Harvard University and a Senior Writer at Law & Liberty. His most recent books are Virtue Politics: Soulcraft and Statecraft in Renaissance Italy and Political Meritocracy in Renaissance Italy.


本文於 修改第 2 次
回應 回應給此人 推薦文章 列印 加入我的文摘
引用網址:https://city.udn.com/forum/trackback.jsp?no=2976&aid=7241323
國家的定義與定位
推薦1


胡卜凱
等級:8
留言加入好友

 
文章推薦人 (1)

胡卜凱

許多研究社會科學或人文科學的學者,常常因為有意無意的使用「擬人化」的論述方式,把思考方向或思考結果搞得不合邏輯(1)(也許這樣大眾才比較容易上當)。我在這裏提供各位20字真言:

「意識無意識,國家無需要,社會無公義,制度不打壓」。

只有「人」才有意識,才有需要,才會假公義之名,滿足私利,才會設計制度來打壓其他的「人」(也就是你和我)。下次你再聽到有人說:「國家需要如何、如何」時,你可以將它翻譯成:「我(說話者)需要如何、如何」。如果你也剛好「需要」如此這般,那你們正好相見歡。如果你並不「需要」如此這般,你大可不必因為她拿「國家」當「我」的代名詞,就幫著她數鈔票。

同樣的,有些人喜歡說:「制度就是如此」。如果你覺得這個「制度」在打壓或剝削你,你要了解︰

打壓或剝削你的不是這個「制度」,是設計這個制度的「人」或「一群人」;以及披著「制度」這張虎皮或扯著「制度」這張大旗的「人」或「一群人」在打壓或剝削你。


除非此「人」是白痴,我敢打賭,99%的情況下,他們做這樣設計,一定有私人的目的。(例如打壓或剝削你、我)。他們這樣做,並沒有,也不需要任何「權利」或「正當性」,只要他們掌握權力就可以了。你大可不必因為他們拿「國家」(社會、憲政、法律等亦同)當冠詞或當「我」的代名詞,就幫著他們數鈔票。你可以選擇在這個「制度」外生活,你也可以選擇顛覆、打破、或重新設計它(2)

後記:

以上摘錄自我在2002年的舊作。我同意「國家觀念」有它一定的功能,但在今天,它已如上述,被濫用到成為貪贓枉法或巧取豪奪的「理由」和「正當性」。在陳某手上,「台獨建國」和「入聯公投」就是這麼玩的。馬先生的「返聯公投」一樣是玩弄「國家觀念」來欺騙老百姓的手法。

可惡和可恨的是,政客們在美國人面前卻坦承自己這種公然欺騙的下三濫行為;更可惡和可恨的是,一些掛著學術羊頭的三客流(該欄2024/07/07 附註1),跳出來替這些下三濫政客擦屁股,還振振有詞的拿什麼「知識論」、「方法論」替自己這種不堪聞問的勾當抹粉。讀書人無恥起來,還真的是叫人感到無法無天。 -- 2011

由於我評論2024諾貝爾經濟學獎三位得主的「研究成果」會引用以上這幾段文字,但又一時找不到它在本城市的位置,所以重登一次。同時略做修改和增加超連接。 -- 11/2024


附註︰

1. 
其他的例子如:哲學家常將歷史、自然、意識等概念「擬人化」,造成許多思考過程上的混淆。如「歷史的法則」、「大自然的反撲」、和「意識的意向性」等。如果改成以下的說法,能避免許多思路上的混淆:「人類活動的法則」、「大自然的變化」、和「一個人思考的意向性」。
2.
這段話只是就理論而言。實際上,一個人通常會考慮行為的後果是否符合他/她生活的目的。如果一個人選擇用暴力來反抗制度,他/她必須面對利用這個制度的人的反撲。我不是在鼓吹以暴制暴,我只是申論它的「正當性」。

本文於 修改第 3 次
回應 回應給此人 推薦文章 列印 加入我的文摘
引用網址:https://city.udn.com/forum/trackback.jsp?no=2976&aid=7240757
美國憲法與聯邦最高法院 ---- Nicholas Reed Langen
推薦1


胡卜凱
等級:8
留言加入好友

 
文章推薦人 (1)

胡卜凱

這篇文章評論齊墨林斯基教授《沒有一個歷久不衰的民主制度》一書。美國憲法和聯邦最高法院都是政治學熱門議題,本欄上一篇也以批評該書開局,故轉登於此。以後再做評論。


America’s Broken Constitution

Nicholas Reed Langen, 10/11/24

While many argue that America’s founding document must be completely overhauled, reforming the Supreme Court may well be sufficient. And with the Electoral College and the Senate politically off-limits, bringing the Court into the twenty-first century may have to suffice.

LONDON – Calling the United States a democracy has become a bit of a stretch. Even the country’s (and the world’s) most feted democratic event is an illusion of popular will. Owing to the Electoral College, most Americans’ votes for president are ultimately irrelevant. The outcome depends not on the collective desire of the American people, but rather on the whims of a tiny sliver of voters in a few counties in a few states.

Legislative elections are little better, thanks to the distortive effects of
gerrymandering, whereby partisan officials draw Dalí-esque electoral districts to benefit their own party. It is a case of politicians choosing their voters, with the skill of the cartographer more important than the wants of the people.

The upshot is that presidents often do not command the confidence of most of the country, and legislators are more interested in pandering to their base than serving the country’s interests. If there was a credible, independent check on these two branches of government, it could keep America on its constitutional rails and prevent politicians from veering off toward autocracy or mob rule. But there is not, because the US constitution is guarded by a Supreme Court whose current members not only embrace political partisanship, but 
wallow in it.

No longer do some justices even pretend to be calling “balls and strikes,” as Chief Justice John Roberts famously 
put it at his confirmation hearing 19 years ago. In the big cases that truly matter, justices ultimately will cleave to their sectarian identities, using politics, rather than the law, as their guide. Although they will cite the text of the Constitution and pay lip service to fundamental judicial principles, these references are there not to ground the decision but to conceal the politics.

A Constitution for Another Time

In 
No Democracy Lasts Forever: How the Constitution Threatens the United States, Erwin Chemerinsky, the dean of Berkeley Law School, concludes that the only solution to America’s constitutional predicament is to start over. If America is to remain a democracy, he argues, tinkering with the system – whether by judicial fiat or constitutional amendment – may not be enough. Only by going back to the beginning might it be possible to undo the fundamental flaws at the core of America’s constitutional order.

Chemerinsky wants us to recognize that no one setting out to establish a democratic political system today would draft anything like the US founding charter. Even if you take the constitution as it was after the Civil War – when slavery finally lost its legal protection, and the franchise had been expanded beyond property-owning men – you would have a fundamentally dysfunctional document. You would have a constitution that valorizes free speech at the cost of true speech, elevates gun ownership above almost everything else, and disproportionately weights the views of citizens who live in states that are more prairie and mountain than city and town.

As Chemerinsky puts it, “the Southern and Midwestern states that have disproportionate power in the Electoral College are red [Republican], while the states with the largest underrepresented urban populations are blue [Democratic].” Couple these structural forces with the country’s changing demographics and you “may make misfire elections much more common.” Wyoming, with a population of 581,000, has the same number of senators as California, with its population of 39 million. Of course, those who cite this statistic often ignore its counterpart: Texas (31 million) has the same number of senators as tiny Rhode Island (1.1 million).

There were good reasons for many of these oddities at the beginning. But that was two and a half centuries ago. Writing at a time when political systems were vulnerable either to tyranny or mob rule, America’s founders were seeking to chart a new course. But they did not assume that they were drafting a document to stand for all time. There was no expectation that what worked in 1787 would work in 2024. On the contrary, the drafters ensured that the constitution could be amended, so that it could grow and develop as the country did. They were crafting “political compromises on all issues,” not declaiming holy writ for the ages.

Missing the Mark

Chemerinsky offers various proposals to update and fix the system, ultimately concluding that America needs a new constitution. His first priority is to abolish or reform the Electoral College. But even if this was done, it would not fundamentally alter the constitutional and political landscape. For all of its absurdities, and for all the attention it gets every four years, the Electoral College has returned a president who lost the popular vote on only 
two occasions since the nineteenth century, when it did so three times.

Yes, those two occasions include two of the last six presidential elections, in 2000 and 2016, both resulting in a Republican victory, and the same could happen again this year. But fixating on the Electoral College ignores the elephant in the room: America is divided down the middle between red and blue. Though the Electoral College benefits Republican presidential candidates, the popular vote would benefit Democrats. The Electoral College nudges the dial for president 
toward the red, and the popular vote would nudge it toward the blue. On this basis alone, the Republican Party will never permit a reform.

Chemerinsky’s second key reform concerns the Senate, where he thinks representation should be reallocated to reflect demography rather than geography. Chemerinsky acknowledges that an equal distribution of senators among the states was “essential to creating the Constitution,” even if it made “the Senate significantly undemocratic from the start.” But it is not clear that it has become less essential, even if the imbalance is “far more disturbing today as the disparity in population … has grown enormously over time.” Parity in the Senate recognizes the contribution of each sovereign state to the American project. Reallocating senators based on population would undermine this. The 50 states may be equal, but some would be more equal than others.

Moreover, Chemerinsky’s solution would elevate America’s urban centers (which lean blue) at the cost of rural districts (which lean red), again raising the question of why a collection of states that cannot agree on even moderate reforms would ever come together to overhaul the entire system. Republicans are fully aware that they benefit from a status quo that rewards geography over demography.

Acknowledging this, Chemerinsky points out that major reforms of America’s political order have always necessarily come during periods of great division, and often at great cost. Most obviously, it took a civil war to abolish slavery. But if an attempted coup and a violent insurrection at the Capitol were not enough to convince Republicans of the need for change, it is unclear what would.

Purblind Justice

Fortunately, there is a more straightforward potential solution. All of the fundamental flaws that Chemerinsky identifies are reparable by the courts, with the exception of senatorial representation and the Electoral College. Gerrymandering, campaign finance, free speech, and other issues can all – and have been – brought before the judiciary. Ever since 
Marbury v. Madison (1803), the Supreme Court’s authority to settle otherwise divisive constitutional matters has been substantial, if not unquestioned.

Since diving headfirst into the thicket of constitutional conundrums at the dawn of the republic, the Court has never retreated. At various points in time, it has affirmed the constitutionality of slavery, upheld gerrymandering, awarded corporations the same right to free speech as citizens, and forbidden states from regulating banks, guns, and health care. It has proven willing to recognize constitutional rights and to take them away. As Alexis de Tocqueville foresaw, every political question in America eventually becomes a judicial one.

But the Supreme Court’s authority per se is not a concern. Though some commentators may bemoan the fact that an unelected body wields such power, the role of the judiciary is a core feature of liberal democracy. It is a vital safeguard to keep the state from going down the path of autocracy or mob rule. But it absolutely is concerning that the Supreme Court has become more of a political body than a judicial one.

True, the Court has never been free of politics and factionalism. Marbury was written by Chief Justice John Marshall, who had served as President John Adams’s Secretary of State before his appointment to the bench. But even if Marshall’s judgment was colored by extrajudicial factors, it ultimately stood on its own two feet. By contrast, later Supreme Court benches have been less adept at casting their political decisions as judicial ones.

Until this century, the most obvious period of apparent politicization was the 1897-1937 
Lochner era, which culminated in the clashes between the Court and President Franklin D. Roosevelt. Five of the Court’s nine justices were vehemently opposed to the New Deal and sought to smother it in its crib. Chief Justice Charles Evans Hughes, a former Republican presidential candidate, consistently joined with the conservative “Four Horsemen” on the Court to strike down flagship policies like the National Industrial Recovery Act of 1933, as well as the Roosevelt administration’s attempts to regulate coal mining and agriculture. Each measure was deemed to lie beyond the constitutional competence of Congress or the White House.

The ostensible intellectual basis for this evisceration of government policy was the Four Horsemen’s commitment to “
originalism.” Insisting that the meaning of the Constitution was fixed at the moment of its ratification, they claimed they were obliged to interpret its text accordingly. Never mind that the founders expressly repudiated this approach. The problem with originalism is not only that it is inconsistent with original intent; it is that it is inconsistent with reality.

As any competent historian would point out, it is impossible to know exactly what historical figures were thinking when they arrived at major decisions. The best that historians can do is offer interpretations or inferences based on the evidence. Unlike Supreme Court justices, they do not presume that their hypotheses should be used to ground contemporary law and policies that affect hundreds of millions of people.

Yet originalism – or at least its bastard child, “
textualism” – persists. Under the guiding hand of the late Antonin Scalia and his acolyte, Clarence Thomas, it became the Court’s most prominent judicial philosophy in recent decades. As Elena Kagan, appointed by President Barack Obama, told the Senate in her confirmation hearing: “We are all originalists now.”

Fight Fire with Water

In the 1930s, Roosevelt prevailed by beating the Four Horsemen at their own political game. Discussing Supreme Court reform during one of his nationally broadcast “
fireside chats,” he asked how the Court could be made to “resume its high task of building anew on the Constitution ‘a system of living law.’” The solution, he proposed, was to add a new justice for every sitting justice over the age of 70. In practice, this would have meant adding six new justices to the bench immediately.

Roosevelt’s “court-packing” scheme made no progress; but nor did he need it to. With the idea of reform wafting through Washington, the next piece of New Deal legislation to come before the court was 
duly upheld. The New Deal was constitutional after all.

US President 
Joe Biden tried to play a similar hand with the reforms he proposed this summer. But like Roosevelt, his proposed reforms would have maintained the Court’s status as a political body first, and a legal one second. For example, introducing term limits and a binding code of ethics might rein in the Court, but it would not alter the politically charged appointment process or the political character of the Court.

Chemerinsky makes the same mistake. He is correct to note that today’s Court has degraded American democracy with decisions like 
Citizens United v. Federal Election Commission (2010), which allowed corporations to “spend unlimited sums” on elections. But in echoing the proposal for judicial term limits, he assumes that judges are “largely insulated from majoritarian politics,” when in fact they are political partisans from the outset. Term limits might address absurdities like the fact that Thomas has been on the Court since some of the lawyers who appear before him were born. But they would not change the fact that Thomas is an unapologetic partisan who will be succeeded by yet another one.

The real challenge for America is to move to a system where judicial decisions are handed down not by “Democratic judges” or “Republican judges,” but just by judges. For Supreme Court justices to be more than “politicians in robes,” the appointment process would need to be completely overhauled.

America the Exceptional

No other country leaves the selection of top judicial officials wholly to the executive and legislative branches. For example, in the United Kingdom, the Lord Chancellor
recommends a candidate to the prime minister, but only after a judicial-appointments commission has completed its due diligence. When a spot on the bench opens up, judges (and senior lawyers) who meet the criteria are invited to apply, and some are short-listed for interviews before a panel of senior judges and lawyers. The Lord Chancellor is the sole partisan voice. After interviewing multiple candidates, the panel makes its recommendation to the government. While the prime minister may reject the nominee, this never happens.

The UK’s appointment process does not ensure that judges are immune from criticism and accusations of political bias; but it does ensure that such blows rarely land. When the UK Supreme Court challenged elements of the government’s strategy to withdraw the country from the European Union, the right-wing media tried to smear the presiding judges as “enemies of the people.” But unlike in the US, where such litigation would have spiraled into a political fracas, these attacks were soon forgotten. The Supreme Court issued its ruling, the government complied, and the UK left the EU in a constitutional fashion.

Much the same goes for other leading liberal democracies, including Canada, Germany, and France. While there may be varying degrees of political involvement in each system, it is always contained, and the judges remain above the partisan fray.

A non-partisan US Supreme Court would bring a politically dispassionate gaze to bear on issues like gerrymandering, abortion, gun rights, or future challenges to an election result. It also could restore some of the credibility it has lost in recent decades. Previously one of the most respected institutions in American politics, with 
approval ratings above 60%, its decisions were generally respected. Under Roberts’s stewardship, however, it has become an institution unworthy of respect and unable to command it. According to the Pew Research Center, a mere 47% of Americans approve of it – a near-historic low. Such findings suggest that even some Trump supporters are skeptical of their pet court.

Chemerinsky argues that the whole constitution needs uprooting, and maybe it does. But reforming the Supreme Court may well be sufficient. And with the Electoral College and the Senate off-limits, bringing the Court into the twenty-first century may have to suffice.


Erwin Chemerinsky, 
No Democracy Lasts Forever: How the Constitution Threatens the United StatesLiveright, 2024.

本文於 修改第 1 次
回應 回應給此人 推薦文章 列印 加入我的文摘
引用網址:https://city.udn.com/forum/trackback.jsp?no=2976&aid=7238875
「『美國的民主政治』研討會」介紹 -- Roger Kimball
推薦1


胡卜凱
等級:8
留言加入好友

 
文章推薦人 (1)

胡卜凱

金博先生這篇文章介紹「『美國的民主政治』研討會。他的主旨在批評美國左翼人士的觀點;可以視為一種「狗咬狗」行為我轉載金博先生大作的原因在於:該文討論到「民主政治」一些內在「困境」以及由它們衍生的流弊

為了幫助大家閱讀,我做了分節的編輯工作,並加上子標題。對美國政情沒什麼興趣的朋友可以略去第016等三節。願意進一步了解「民主政治」的朋友,則不妨仔細玩味第2345各節。

做為文藝評論家,金博先生顯然有舞文弄墨的癖好,我只得花點時間做些註解;希望小有幫助。

索引:

ad hoc
:特別的,專門的,為了特定需要的
Alinsky, Saul
apostrophize
apostrophe為「所有格」符號;此「動詞」形式指「加上『所有格』符號」;除了看得出諷刺意味外,我並不很清楚金博先生此處的「用法」。
assiduously
:勤勉地,不懈地,周到地,用盡吃奶的力氣地
chaperon
:監護,監護者,貴族或富家社會中陪伴未婚少女出現在公共場所的年長女伴
circumscribing
:限制,限定,約束,畫界線,
co-opt
:推舉爲新成員,強行拉進,吸收,拉攏,籠絡,據為己有,借用(別人的觀點);此處:收編
coda
:結尾,尾聲;此處:跋
de Tocqueville, Alexis:法國學者、外交官,以《美國的民主政治》一書聞名
dhimmitude:順民
diktats:強加於失敗方的法律、處罰、或處分;強制命令
dysfunctional
失衡的,不正常的,機能障礙的,無法運作的
Electoral College
:選舉人團
epithet
:表示特徵的修飾詞;(褒貶人時使用的)渾名,綽號,稱號
ergo
:所以;笛卡爾的名句:Cogito, ergo sum (「我思,『故』我在」)
extralegal
:非法定的,無法源的
eulogistic
(原指悼詞中)稱頌的,頌揚的,贊美的;此處為諷刺意,相當於我常常說的:「擦脂抹粉」(見此字後作者接著用的 ”advertising”)
franchise
:此處:公民權,選舉權;公民,選民
genuflect
(尤指進出天主教教堂時)下跪,跪拜;引申為:跪拜,屈服,卑躬屈膝
Lewis, C. S.
Madison, James
nomenklatura(共產黨術語)指經過篩選可出任黨職或地方官員者的名單;相當於共產黨文宣中的的「無產階級先鋒隊」;引申為:掌權集團,權力核心,新階級
nota bene
:請務必注意下面說的
ochlocracy
:暴民政治
Potter, Stephen
quaint
:別緻的,(尤指)古雅的(觀點、信仰或行為方式),奇怪的,不合邏輯的,過時的,老式的,古早味的
Quod erat demonstrandum
:證明完畢,簡寫為QED
remonstrate
 抗議,反對,進諫,告誡,表達異議
secession
:從國家或團體中分離出去,另行建立一個獨立國家或新的團體。
The Narrative
:主流論述,流行思潮;請參見「大論述(我有時將此概念譯為「鬼話」、「神話」)
The New Criterion:《新標準》,一份有保守主義傾向的文學/藝術評論雜誌;請參考The New Criterion -- Bias and Credibility金博先生為該刊主編兼發行人
the Swamp:請參見Swamp
visceral
:內臟的;此處:出自內心深處的


Democracy in America: an introduction

Roger Kimball, October 2024

On the trouble with democracy in America.

Editors’ note: “Democracy in America: a symposium” examines the status of popular sovereignty in the United States today, nearly two centuries after the seminal work of the political theorist Alexis de Tocqueville. Other participants include 
Victor Davis HansonDaniel J. MahoneyJames Piereson & Glenn Ellmers.

Almost all the rulers who have tried to destroy freedom have at first attempted to preserve its forms. This has been seen from Augustus down to our own day.

— Alexis de Tocqueville, The Old Regime and the Revolution (1856)

0. 
前言

Democracy in America: what is it? Whatever it is, we know that it is under siege. Barely a moment goes by these days without tocsins sounding about various threats to “our democracy” (I’ll come back to that plural possessive below). It used to be that the biggest, baddest threat to “our democracy” was Donald Trump (I’ll come back to that, too). Then a curious thing happened. Trump still gets prominent billing, ex officio, as it were, but when it comes to “threats to our democracy,” he seems to have been overshadowed somewhat by a curious new threat: the Constitution.

How can that be, you ask? Isn’t the Constitution of the United States, in addition to being our founding document and the arbiter of what is lawful and what isn’t, the fundamental guarantor of “our democracy”? That was yesterday. Today, if you are truly up-to-date, you know that the Constitution, while venerable, is basically at odds with democracy. “We Had to Force the Constitution to Accommodate Democracy, and It Shows,” reads one headline in The New York TimesLet’s Give Up on the Constitution,” reads another. “The U.S. Lacks What Every Democracy Needs,” reads a third, whose column goes on to lament “the high cost of living with an old Constitution.”

1. 
左派對美國憲法的批判

The fact that the U.S. Constitution is—by far—the world’s longest-serving constitution used to be a point of pride. Now, for some activists, that longevity is an embarrassment as well as an affront. The New York Times may have long since abandoned its pretensions to bringing its readers the news, preferring instead to batten them on whatever The Narrative demands. But, considered as a barometer of the vacillating pressures of left-wing political fashion, the paper has grown ever more sensitive. The culmination of its campaign against the Constitution came on August 31 with a column by Jennifer Szalai entitled “The Constitution Is Sacred. Is It Also Dangerous?” According to Szalai, the answer is Yes. “One of the biggest threats to America’s politics,” we read in its subtitle, “might be the country’s founding document.” Really?

It wasn’t so long ago that organs like the Times complained that Donald Trump was “a menace to the Constitution.” (Another headline from the Times: “maga Turns Against the Constitution.”) But the new memo blames the Constitution for giving us Trump. Hence the new hotness is the contention that “Trump owes his political ascent to the Constitution, making him a beneficiary of a document that is essentially antidemocratic and, in this day and age, increasingly dysfunctional.” The Constitution allowed Donald Trump to become president. Ergo the Constitution is “dysfunctional.” Quod erat demonstrandum.

Szalai leans heavily in her column on the left-wing law professor Erwin Chemerinsky and his new book No Democracy Lasts Forever: How the Constitution Threatens the United States
1 It is almost too good to be true, but it is true that Chemerinsky is a professor at the University of California at Berkeley. Accordingly, there is no left-wing piety—about women, blacks, immigrants, January 6, Donald Trump, Republicans, and many other things—to which he neglects to genuflect or remonstrate, as the case requires. He even gives the thoroughly discredited Russia-collusion hoax another go-around and argues that, in the age of the internet, “false speech poses a serious threat to democracy.” And who gets to decide what counts as “false speech,” Professor?

Chemerinsky’s basic argument is that the Constitution, inadequate in 1787 when it was first adopted, has totally outlived whatever dubious usefulness it once had. He lavishes special animus on the Electoral College (which makes it possible for a candidate to win the popular vote but lose the election), the provision of two senators for every state, regardless of its size or population, and the Supreme Court, which also, he says, “undermines democracy” because it’s too independent and life tenure insulates justices from public opinion. (Wasn’t that precisely what the framers had in mind with Article III?) In conclusion, Chemerinsky predicts, “the time will come when Americans will realize that the Constitution itself is endangering democracy and they will start thinking of replacing it.” And if that doesn’t work, he says, there is always secession. Most legal scholars believe that the 1869 decision Texas v. White declared secession unconstitutional. But that doesn’t faze Chemerinsky: he disputes the common reading of the decision and argues that, regardless, secession can mean many things and can take a variety of forms.

Chemerinsky begins the brief coda to his book with the declaration: “Our government is broken and our democracy is at grave risk.” Again, what is that “democracy” of which he speaks? When Benjamin Franklin, emerging from the Constitutional Convention in 1787, was asked what sort of government he and his colleagues had forged, he famously said “A republic, if you can keep it.” A republicnota bene, not a democracy. The difference is critical.

2. 
民主制度」及其流弊 -- 1

As Victor Davis Hanson notes below in his essay on “Our Athenian American Democracy,” “republics inevitably face an innate and radically democratizing opposition, which always seeks,” via “court edicts, referenda, or internal coups,” to “alter ‘mixed’ constitutions and restore the unchecked power of the people, or at least of its often-tyrannical leaders and institutional advocates.”

Among the many reasons that it is difficult to keep a republic going is the constant pressure to transform one party into the party of the regime. This indeed was the primary reason that the founders were suspicious of political parties. They worried that the growth of political parties would lead to what they called “faction,” and faction was a standing invitation to corruption. It works like this: A portion of the voting populace is in effect co-opted by politicians who promise and deliver favors in exchange for votes, which fosters a culture of corruption. You scratch my back and I bequeath you the legislative apparatus of the state, till bankruptcy do us part, and maybe not even then. This is the origin of “the Swamp.”

Originally, as Hanson also notes, “democracy” meant rule by “the demos,” the people. But as George Orwell pointed out in his novel Animal Farm, there is a moral or political entropy at work in human affairs that, unchecked, regularly perverts “the people” into “some people.” All animals are equal, you see, but some are more equal than others. As an aside, it is worth mentioning that the prevalence of this degeneration in the human heart is one reason that most political theorists, from Plato and Aristotle on down, have been profoundly suspicious of “pure,” direct, unchaperoned democracy. Aristotle thought it the worst form of government, leading almost inevitably to ochlocracy, or mob rule. James Madison, in Federalist 10, warned that throughout history most democracies have been as “short in their lives as they have been violent in their deaths.” “Theoretic politicians,” he wrote—and it would be hard to find a more contemptuous deployment of the word “theoretic”—may have advocated democracy, but that is only because of their dangerous and utopian ignorance of human nature. It was not at all clear, Madison thought, that democracy was a reliable custodian of liberty.

Nevertheless, nearly everyone wants to associate himself with the word “democracy.” Totalitarian regimes like to describe themselves as the “Democratic Republic” of wherever. Conservatives champion the advantages of “democratic capitalism.” Central planners of all stripes eagerly deploy programs advertised as enhancing or extending “democracy.” Columnists for The New York Times and Berkeley law professors attack the Constitution because it stands in the way of certain democratic impulses. “Democracy,” in short, is a eulogistic word, what the practical philosopher Stephen Potter in another context apostrophized as an “OK word.” And it is worth noting, as Potter would have been quick to remind us, that the people pronouncing those eulogies delight in advertising themselves as, and are generally accepted as, “OK people.” Indeed, the class element and the element of moral approbation—of what some sage has summarized as “virtue signaling”—are key.

3. 
聯邦論者的民主制度護欄」

It was part of Madison’s genius, supported by Alexander Hamilton and the other founders, to have forged a species of popular rule that carefully modulated the passions of the masses in such a way that protected individual liberty in the face of the imperatives of democracy. Hence the Electoral College, which is a primary mechanism for preserving federalism. Hence, too, two senators to every state: why should Wyoming, say, be swamped by the ethos of California? Such expedients are not bugs but features of a dispensation whose aim is to preserve a canvas for individual liberty. You may have noticed that the loudest voices among Democrats chanting about “our democracy” aren’t much interested in preserving individual liberty. They’re interested instead in the acquisition and retention of power, on the one hand, and the exercise of social control, on the other.

There is a sense, then, in which Chemerinsky and like-minded critics are right about the Constitution being “antidemocratic.” It is antidemocratic in the sense that it is pro-republic. Which is to say that the Constitution is primarily about circumscribing the coercive power of the government. As Madison famously put it in Federalist 51, “In framing a government which is to be administered by men over men, the great difficulty lies in this: you must first enable the government to control the governed; and in the next place oblige it to control itself.” The limits on federal power set forth in the Constitution make it a bulwark against many sorts of abuse, including that most constant temptation of democracies, the tyranny of the majority.

To some extent, “democracy” is a positive but empty epithet. When Chemerinsky complains that the Constitution is “antidemocratic,” the democracy he has in mind is not the same democracy that Ronald Reagan invoked when he observed that “democracy is less a system of government than it is a system to keep government limited, unintrusive: a system,” Reagan continued, “of constraints on power to keep politics and government secondary to the important things in life, the true sources of value found only in family and faith.”

Whether what Reagan says is true of democracy itself is something that we might, with Tocqueville, and with sadness, want to question. Too often democracy has been prey to deformations that encourage rather than retard the growth of government, as Daniel J. Mahoney demonstrates in his essay below. That indeed was part of what the founders had to conjure with as they combed through the graveyard of history’s failed democracies in their efforts to frame a more robust and long-lasting system of government.

Can anyone read what Madison said about the Constitution delegating to the federal government only powers that are “few and defined” without a smile? How quaint it all sounds to our ears. And what do we make of the observation, from Federalist 57, that the people would never tolerate a law that was “not obligatory on the legislature, as well as on the people”?

4. 
「民主制度」的內在困境

Article I of the Constitution vests all legislative power in the Congress. But for many decades now, Congress has been assiduously avoiding that duty. As the political philosopher James Burnham noted back in the 1940s in The Managerial Revolution: What Is Happening in the World, laws in the United States were, even then, increasingly being made not by Congress, but by an alphabet soup of executive-branch agencies. And note that Burnham wrote decades before the advent of such monstrosities as the epahud, the cfpb, the Department of Education, and the rest of the administrative agglomeration that governs us in the United States today. More and more, we are ruled not by laws but by ad hoc diktats emanating from semiautonomous and largely unaccountable quasi-governmental bureaucracies, many of which meet in secret but whose proclamations have the force, though not the legitimacy, of law.

Indeed, Americans today find their lives directed by a jumble of agencies far removed from the legislature and staffed by bureaucrats who make and enforce a vast network of rules that govern nearly every aspect of our lives. Who defines the scope of those rules? It is difficult to say. This is the puzzle that James Piereson underscores below in “The Washington octopus.”

What is “discrimination” under the Civil Rights Act? What is the definition of “clean air” or “pollution” under the Clean Air Act? How do we define “sex discrimination” under Title IX—indeed, how do we define “sex” or “gender”? How do we define “ballot access” under the Voting Rights Act? What is the definition of “transparency” under the mandate of the Securities Exchange Commission (sec)? The laws as passed by Congress do not answer these questions in any detail. As a consequence, civil servants have latitude to define those terms, and to issue regulations that follow from them, with little oversight from Congress. Laws may be congressional in origin, but they are now mostly administrative or bureaucratic in content.

We have entered the vertiginous realm of the “administrative state,” what Glenn Ellmers below calls the “nonconsensual rule of America’s managerial class.”

One of the most disturbing features of this phenomenon was exposed by Philip Hamburger in his work on the history and evolution of the administrative state. As Hamburger notes, the expansion of the franchise in the early twentieth century went hand in hand with the growth of administrative, that is to say, extralegal, power. For the people in charge, equality of voting rights was one thing. They could live with that. But the tendency of newly enfranchised groups—the “bitter clingers” and “deplorables” of yore—to reject progressive initiatives was something else again. That was unacceptable.

5. 
民主制度」及其流弊 -- 2

In 2016, Donald Trump was elected in a free, open, and democratic election. But the nomenklatura screamed that his election was illegitimate, a challenge to democracy, because—why? Because the wrong person wonThat was Trump’s tort: he was a threat to “our democracy” because he won, because people voted for him.

Woodrow Wilson, a standard-bearer for an earlier incarnation of the progressive juggernaut, epitomized this elitist spirit. “The bulk of mankind,” he noted sadly, “is rigidly unphilosophical, and nowadays the bulk of mankind votes.” What to do? The solution was to shift real power out of elected bodies and into the hands of the right sort of people, enlightened people, progressive people, people, that is to say, like Woodrow Wilson. Therefore, Wilson welcomed the advent of administrative power as a counterweight to encroaching democratization. And thus it was, as Hamburger points out, that we have seen a transfer of legislative power to the “knowledge class,” the managerial elite—the “new ruling class” that James Burnham anatomized.

A closer look at the so-called knowledge class shows that what it knows best is how to preserve and extend its own privileges. Its activities are swaddled in do-gooder rhetoric about serving the public, promoting democracy, looking after “the environment,” helping the disadvantaged, fighting racism, and similar performative kindnesses. But what they chiefly excel at is consolidating and extending their own power.

Who staffs this new elite? That, too, is a difficult question to answer. Elsewhere, I have called the governing entity “The Committee.” I do not know exactly who populates it. Vivek Ramaswamy touched on the sponginess of the situation when he noted that with Kamala Harris, Republicans are “not running against a candidate. We’re running against a system. They require a candidate they can control, which means having original ideas is a disqualification.” But who is “they”? Exactly who, for example, told Joe Biden that he had to go, the voters be damned? Whoever it was, you can be sure that they’re on The Committee.

C. S. Lewis touched on the broader psychological or moral dimension of this phenomenon in a lecture called “The Inner Ring.” In every social organization, Lewis wrote, there exist two hierarchies. One is an official and public hierarchy. The other is covert. The names of its members are “not printed anywhere.”

Nor is it even a formally organised secret society with officers and rules which you would be told after you had been admitted. You are never formally and explicitly admitted by anyone. You discover gradually, in almost indefinable ways, that it exists and that you are outside it; and then later, perhaps, that you are inside it. . . . It is not easy, even at a given moment, to say who is inside and who is outside. Some people are obviously in and some are obviously out, but there are always several on the borderline.

6. 
結論

Many commentators have noted the profoundly undemocratic maneuver with which The Committee erased Joe Biden and installed Kamala Harris as the Democratic presidential nominee. After all, nearly fifteen million people voted for Joe Biden in the Democratic primary. He won, hands down, because those who inhabit the Inner Ring of The Committee made certain that other candidates—including Robert F. Kennedy Jr.—were shunted to one side. They had done the same thing to Bernie Sanders years before. All, of course, in the name of “democracy.”

Which brings me to the distinction between “democracy” and “our democracy.” The latter poaches on the authority and prestige of the former. But what it really means is “their oligarchy,” “their prerogative.” As I have noted elsewhere, honestly parsed, the phrase “our democracy” means “rule by Democrats.” Accordingly, to such questions as “Was the election fair?,” what you first need to know in order to answer is, “Who won?” If it was the Democrats, then the election was fair. If the Democrats lost, then the election was stolen.

There are further things worth bearing in mind as we contemplate the political distempers of the times. One concerns the hardening of the Left. Barack Obama’s victory in 2008, followed by the incomprehensible victory of Donald Trump, has radicalized and emboldened the Left.

Today, the Left says things they would hitherto only have thought and does things that they would hitherto only have said. It used to be that there was a certain latitude accorded to opposing views. That’s all over now. What we see is the triumph not just of political correctness but also of visceral intolerance that nurtures a “by-any-means-necessary” attitude. Every issue is an existential emergency for which the Left’s shock troops are willing to go to the wall. Every loss demands that people scream at the sky. We win or we threaten to burn everything down. At least since Trump’s victory, the dominant attitude has been that only the Left is allowed to win. Any conservative victory is by definition illegitimate, a blow to “our democracy.”

It seems to me that conservatism has three main choices. One is outright surrender. One is the dhimmitude of the well-pressed but housebroken Right that exchanges its pampered place on the plantation for political irrelevance. The third choice is the perhaps paradoxical option of what we might call Alinskyite conservatism, after the canny left-wing activist Saul Alinsky. This option eschews the quietism of surrender for the activism of what Donald Trump calls “winning.”

How is this to be accomplished? As Piereson suggests below, one major goal must be to downgrade the place of Washington, the city as well as the spirit it entails, in the metabolism of American political life. Piereson is quite correct—it is an important insight—that notwithstanding its overwhelmingly Democratic coloration, the capital has developed into a kind of “political party in its own right.” Its triumph stands behind the real threat to the republic bequeathed to us by the founders. That threat is not the Constitution but subservience to the faceless managerial elite that exercises the real power in our society. Legitimacy is draining out of our governing institutions at an alarming rate. Stanching that debilitating flow requires that we redirect our attention away from the greedy puppet show in Washington to the true source of legitimacy, which is with the people.

1.  No Democracy Lasts Forever: How the Constitution Threatens the United States, by Erwin Chemerinsky; Liveright, 240 pages, $29.99 


Roger Kimball is Editor and Publisher of The New Criterion and President and Publisher of Encounter Books. His latest books include 
The Critical Temper: Interventions from The New Criterion at 40 (Encounter Books) and Where Next? Western Civilization at the Crossroads (Encounter Books).

A MESSAGE FROM THE EDITORS

New to The New Criterion?

Become a subscriber to receive ten print issues and gain immediate access to our online archive spanning more than four decades of art and cultural criticism.
Subscribe



本文於 修改第 1 次
回應 回應給此人 推薦文章 列印 加入我的文摘
引用網址:https://city.udn.com/forum/trackback.jsp?no=2976&aid=7238375
柏拉圖的5種政府形式 -- Dave Roos
推薦1


胡卜凱
等級:8
留言加入好友

 
文章推薦人 (1)

胡卜凱

What Are Plato’s 5 Forms of Government?

In Plato's 'Republic,' the ancient Greek philosopher lays out five different forms of government, ranging from ideal to oppressive.

Dave Roos, 09/05/24

Plato’s Republic is one of the foundational texts of Western philosophy and political thought. Written as a lively dialogue between Socrates and, among others, Plato’s brothers, the Republic offers a sweeping examination of “justice” and how it might be achieved—or not achievedpolitically.

For most of the book, 
Plato presents the philosophical arguments for the highest form of government: an aristocracy ruled by wise and virtuous philosophers. Whether or not such an “idealized” state could ever exist in practice is an open question. The Republic wasn’t meant to be a historical examination of existing forms of government, but a philosophical discussion of pros and cons of different hypothetical political “regimes.”

“For Plato, the purpose of government is to advance human excellence and advance human virtue,” says 
Mark Blitz, a professor of political philosophy at Claremont McKenna College in California. “Ultimately for Plato, the ‘best’ form of government turns out to be the rule of philosophers. But the fundamental questions of the Republic are: What is justice? And what are the limits of justice politically?”

Those limitations are on full display in Book VIII of the Republic, in which Socrates discusses the inferior forms of government ranked in descending order: oligarchy, timocracy, democracy and tyranny

1. Aristocracy (
)

In Greek, the word “aristocracy” literally means “the rule of the best.” For Plato, an aristocracy wasn’t a society ruled by a wealthy class of elites or nobles—as we might think of it today—but a society led by its greatest citizens. Socrates describes these rulers as “the best philosophers and the bravest warriors” who are dedicated to the common good.  

“‘Philosophy’ in Ancient Greece wasn’t the narrow academic discipline that we treat it as now,” says Blitz. “Philosophy meant the full study of human things, including mathematics, the natural sciences and politics.”

The philosopher-rulers of Plato’s ideal state would be selected from childhood for their moral character and physical talents. Promising candidates would be educated and trained in the superiority of reason and the bridling of passions. The best among these philosophers would rule together as wise and benevolent kings.

To avoid temptation and corruption, Plato’s philosopher rulers wouldn’t receive any income or be able to own private property. They would share everything in common with their fellow guardians—even their wives and children would be held in common.

For Plato, a society ruled by philosophers exercising the highest moral, ethical and political judgment would provide the greatest chance for its citizens to experience true justice, happiness and peace.

But Plato must have also known that such a government was “if not literally impossible, at least extraordinarily unlikely,” says Blitz, author of 
Plato’s Political Philosophy. “What Plato meant by a true philosopher—you can probably count on two hands and two feet the number that have ever lived! You’re talking about Aristotle, Locke, Hegel… In a single generation, you may not have any of these extraordinary figures, let alone a few of them.”

Because Plato recognized that a true philosophical aristocracy—if achievable—would be short-lived, he used Book VIII of the Republic to describe lesser forms of government.

2. Timocracy (
財閥政)

Each of the lesser “regimes,” to Plato, was dominated by a different type of human character (or character flaw). A timocracy is a society ruled by those who love honor above all else. Blitz says that ancient Sparta is a useful (if imperfect) example of a timocracy. It was a society “devoted to war and the honor of the warrior” rather than to full excellence.

In the Republic, when Socrates is asked to describe the character of those who are attracted to a timocracy, he says, “[H]e is a lover of power and a lover of honor; claiming to be a ruler, not because he is eloquent, or on any ground of that sort, but because he is a soldier and has performed feats of arms; he is also a lover of gymnastic exercises and of the chase.”

Plato talks a lot about the “soul” in the Republic. The body, Plato explains, is merely an instrument for the immortal soul, which can be “corrupted by vice and purified by virtue.” The soul of a true philosopher, therefore, is dominated by reason. The soul of the timocrat is dominated by “spiritedness” (thumos in Greek), what Blitz describes as “the seat of anger, pride and love of honor.”

There’s nothing “wrong” with loving honor, says Blitz, “it’s just insufficient. It’s not the full devotion to reason,” which Plato holds as the highest condition of the soul. A timocracy, while inferior to an aristocracy, is at least focused on the common good. That can’t be said for the next regime, the oligarchy.

3. Oligarchy (
寡頭政)

One of the most dangerous aspects of a timocracy, for Plato, was how quickly it could degrade into an oligarchy. In an oligarchy, the love of honor is replaced with a selfish and insatiable love of money.

In the Republic, Socrates describes an oligarchy as, “A government resting on a valuation of property, in which the rich have power and the poor man is deprived of it…[where] one, seeing another grow rich, seeks to rival him, and thus the great mass of the citizens become lovers of money…and so they grow richer and richer, and the more they think of making a fortune the less they think of virtue…and in proportion as riches and rich men are honored in the state, virtue and the virtuous are dishonored.”

Plato understood the irresistible draw of money and its corrupting influence on rulers. That’s why, in his perfect society, the philosopher-kings would be paid only in food and shelter, and not allowed to own or accumulate property. When wealth and property are prized above all else, power is concentrated in the hands of a privileged few who will stop at nothing to acquire more.

For Plato, economic growth and economic expansion weren’t political concerns like they are in capitalist democracies today.

“In general, Plato would have looked askance at the whole project of economic growth and human accumulation,” says Blitz. 

4. Democracy (
民主政體)

Plato didn’t celebrate “freedom,” “liberty” and “equality” as requirements for a just society. In fact, Plato’s major gripe with democracy was that it resulted in an “excess of liberty.”

For Plato, one of the challenges of the human condition was to choose between “necessary” and “unnecessary” desires. In an aristocracy, that’s not a problem because the philosopher-rulers will use their superior abilities to desire only those things that result in the common good. Even timocrats and oligarchs will channel their energy toward certain “necessary,” if inferior desires: honor and wealth.

The problem with a true democracy—and Plato knew the original Athenian version, warts and all—was that the government operated at the whim of individual desires, which in many cases were “unnecessary” and at odds with the greater good.

“There’s freedom in a democracy, but that freedom is not directed,” says Blitz. “It’s open to any kind of desire, which can lead to a kind of lowering or degrading of society.”

That’s why Plato wasn’t a big fan of “equality,” either. In his mind, not every citizen was cut out for a leadership role. Decisions affecting broader society should be left in the hands of the “best” among them. That wasn’t confined to a certain class or family line, but determined by talent and training.

In the Republic, Plato places democracy below oligarchy, because he sees it as the natural step following a revolution. When the poor grow tired of injustice, they will overthrow the oligarchs and use the tools of democracy to “deprive the rich of their estates and distribute them among the people,” says Socrates. 

It is this same populist “mob” mentality, in Plato’s reasoning, that allows for the rise of the tyrant.

5. Tyranny (
獨夫政體)

How does the tyrant come to power? By masquerading as the “protector” of the people.

“The people have always some champion whom they set over them and nurse into greatness,” says Socrates in the Republic. “This and no other is the root from which a tyrant springs; when he first appears above ground he is a protector.”

Once the tyrant gains the support of the mob, he turns against his enemies and critics, using the courts to execute or banish them. The tyrant constantly stirs up wars to rally his supporters against a foreign enemy and distract them from the fact that their lives aren’t improving. Once the people realize they’ve given the tyrant too much power, it’s too late. Their lives are fully in his control.

The tyrant, in Plato’s political view, is the alter ego of the philosopher. Where the philosopher is only concerned with the common good, the tyrant only cares about himself and his inner circle. Where the philosopher is in control of his “unnecessary” desires, the tyrant shows no restraint whatsoever.

“Plato’s argument in the Republic is that the tyrant is the most unjust and least happy, and that the philosopher is the most just soul and therefore the happiest,” says Blitz.


Dave Roos is a journalist and podcaster based in the U.S. and Mexico. He's the co-host of Biblical Time Machine, a history podcast, and a writer for the popular podcast Stuff You Should Know. Learn more at daveroos.com.

Citation Information


Article Title
What Are Plato’s 5 Forms of Government?
Author
Dave Roos
Website Name
HISTORY
URL
https://www.history.com/news/what-are-platos-5-forms-of-government
Date Accessed
September 13, 2024
Publisher
A&E Television Networks
Last Updated
September 5, 2024
Original Published Date
September 5, 2024


HISTORY Vault: Ancient History

From Egypt to Greece, explore fascinating documentaries about the ancient world.
WATCH NOW

Ancient Empires

Watch the three-episode documentary event, Ancient Empires. Available to stream now.
WATCH NOW

本文於 修改第 1 次
回應 回應給此人 推薦文章 列印 加入我的文摘
引用網址:https://city.udn.com/forum/trackback.jsp?no=2976&aid=7237165
公平、自由、和不應如何做學問
推薦1


胡卜凱
等級:8
留言加入好友

 
文章推薦人 (1)

胡卜凱

0.  前言

我想瓦爾頓教授大作的重點在介紹康德的「權利中心論」(本欄上一篇);她指出羅爾斯和婁澤克兩位理論的不足,來襯托或彰顯康德理論的優越。羅爾斯在台灣應該蠻受歡迎我也沒有讀完整本公平論我就不多說他(1)。本城市在2011刊登過關於婁澤克和他思想的討論。有興趣的朋友可以參考。

我對康德的思想沒有熟悉到可以置喙的地步;以下只就「公平」、「自由」、和「做學問」這三個議題略抒己見。

1. 
公平

我曾說過,「權利」不是「天賦」的;它是爭來的,搶來的,某些人甚至要用生命換的。「公平」不是「權利」,它也並不具有任何「應然性」或「高貴性」。換句話說,如果一個人覺得社會待他/她「不公平」,通常此人只能「喊冤」、「告狀」、「抬棺材」、「丟雞蛋」、和「拉白布條」等等。如果困難不得解決,他/她可以繼之以「丟炸彈」、「上梁山泊」、或「冒充耶穌的兄弟」之類。當然/她也可以摸摸鼻子或跳樓、臥軌

一般而言,「公平」不過是維持社會穩定運作的一個概念或參數。我們可以把它看成是測量一個社會「穩定度」的指標

一個社會的「公平性」越高,這個社會的「穩定度」也就越高。反之,一個「公平性」低的社會,將經常處於紛爭、衝突的狀況,最後導致動亂內戰或崩潰。

如果以上的分析有幾分道理,我建議

「政府」的「功能」或「責任」之一,是維持,以及盡可能提高社會的「公平性」。

我這個理論應該比康德繞來繞去的論述淺顯易懂;根據它推論出來的政策,也會比根據康德說法推論出來的政策,更具「可行性」,也能更有效解決社會的不穩定狀況。

上述觀點我以前表達過很多次,只是呈現方式有所不同。請參考《探討民主政治》一文。

2. 
自由

2.1
自由的本質

拙作《重新檢視「個人主義」和「自由主義」》一文中,已經把我所了解的「自由」說得很清楚。以下特別強調其中兩點:

1) 
「『自由』行為」不得打擾到他人,更不得侵犯他人的權利和利益。否則,它們不得稱為「『自由』行為」,而應該叫做「『吃人夠夠』行為」。
2) 
「公平性」蘊含:保障每一個社會成員具有行使最基本「『自由』行為」的能力。

至於「打擾」、「侵犯」、「權利」、「利益」、「保障」、「能力」、和「最基本「『自由』行為」等詞彙指示些什麼,由每個社會的成員們自行協商決定。

2.2
自由的「羊頭性」

許多人臉皮薄,不好意思明目張膽的維護自己擁有的「特權」(2);於是拿「自由」來當做護身符。其伎倆是:號稱自己在維護「公民『自由』權」(3)。但是,這些人口中的「自由」,指的其實是你、我眼中的「特權」。

3. 
「自由」和「公平」有衝突?

如果看官們同意以上12兩節的看法,不但不會認為「公平」和「自由」之間有衝突;反而會跟我一樣,認為兩者相輔相成:

「自由」是爭取「公平」的武器;「公平」是維護「自由」的機制。

許多人往往因為思路有盲點,或思考時不自覺的歪七扭八打著轉,以至於搞不清楚一對相關的概念。例如「自由」和「平等」;又如「自由」和「民主」等等。我對它們做過一些釐清和分析的工作;前者請見此欄,後者請讀此文;並敬請指正。

4. 
學者們思路混亂的源頭

我在第1節中用「繞來繞去」一詞形容康德的論述,並無不敬之意;只是單純表達我的讀後感。學者們或許想把自己思想的來龍去派說得清楚精緻一些;或許想增加自己主張的說服性;或許只不過想掉掉書袋;總之,其結果往往成為學者們把簡單事務變複雜了。在這個過程中,一不小心,他/門的思路也變混亂了。第3節觸及的議題則是此傾向的兩個特例。

根據拙作《「政治」答客問》一文的淺見,我歸納出三個研究社會科學的要點(4)

1) 
人生活的目的在求生存下去和生活得舒適」;生存下去」和生活得舒適」都需要資源;所以,追求資源或一般人說的貪婪」,實際上是每個人生活」下去的自然反應」正常行為」。
2) 
任何一個地區(或社會)(任何)資源都不夠當地人的需求」(5);從而巧取豪奪」和「坑矇拐騙」即使不是每個人的自然反應」正常行為」,事實上它們都在許多人的「行為選項範圍之內
3) 
以上兩段話中的每個人」,嚴格的說,在統計上可能只包括任何社會中95%左右的人;從而,即使不是每個人」都如此這般,以上兩段話所描述的情況,涵蓋了政府官員、教授教員、和尚牧師、男女老幼等各行各業的人士

我不是說,任何社會中95%左右的人是壞人」;我說的是,正如重賞之下必有勇夫」;在厚利當前」時刻,社會中95%左右的人都有貪贓枉法、偷雞摸狗、男盜女娼的傾向

面對和接受以上所描述的現實,我們才能有效的設計出

一套維持社會穩定運作的制度和機制;也才能落實「公平」、「自由」、和「權利」這些概念

不肯面對和接受這個現實,再多幾個九彎十八拐的理論,也不過是為了混飯吃而製造論文乃至於廢紙

5. 
結論

社會科學的理論要解決「人」的問題。要解決「人」的問題,就必須面對一個個活生生,需要吃、喝、拉、撒、和炒飯的「人」

「人」不是抽象的概念,不是籃球高手不是幕後木偶也的確不是工具但只要有機會和權力,他/她在95%左右的場合下,會把另一個「人」當工具來增加自己的資源以及存活機會

附註:

1. 我讀過兩三本介紹/批評《公平論》的書,如阿樂杭卓教授的羅爾斯公平」概念的侷限,他認為羅爾斯的「正義即公平」理論矛盾(或推論漏洞)百出
2.
這些「特權」可能來自:祖上靠騎馬打仗發家的,如歐洲各國貴族後裔;老子是幹走私的,如甘迺迪家族;老子是幹革命的,如薄熙來、習近平
3.
婁澤克是公民自由權論」的大師請見瓦爾頓教授大作和本文第0節中的超連結。本城市2013-2014刊登了幾篇討論教宗方濟針對全球經濟狀況所做宣示的文章;該欄開欄文2013/12/16貼文2014/02/01貼文討論到此一思想。亦請參考此文
4
. 前幾天整理舊作時,無意間看到2005年我和兩位網友討論社會科學「方法論」的文章其中一位以英文賜教,我也以英文回應。對此議題有興趣的朋友,請前往此欄瀏覽(該欄共有4)
5
. 拙作《交換價值和資源分配》對此觀點有更細緻的分析。

本文於 修改第 4 次
回應 回應給此人 推薦文章 列印 加入我的文摘
引用網址:https://city.udn.com/forum/trackback.jsp?no=2976&aid=7230909
羅爾斯和婁澤克:公平或自由? -- Helga Varden
推薦1


胡卜凱
等級:8
留言加入好友

 
文章推薦人 (1)

胡卜凱

這篇文章點出兩個重要的概念:公平和自由雖然我並不熟悉康德羅爾斯和婁澤克的著作但對他們三位的思想算得上略有所知。我會略為討論瓦爾頓教授的大作;也很想聽聽各位對公平」和「自由」的看法。


Rawls vs Nozick: Justice or Freedom?

The answer depends on what kind of freedom you want

Helga Varden, 06/06/24

Whether we want justice or freedom is the central political question behind all our political disputes – we have Rawls and Nozick to thank for this. In modern politics, the left is associated with seeking justice: we find this in ideas of equality and social justice. The right, on the other hand, is associated with the protection of a libertarian notion of freedom. We must move beyond this divide, argues Helga Varden. Some freedoms are worth fighting for more than others, and some freedoms cannot be pursued by everyone until we undo the existing injustice present in the system. – Editor’s Notes


In the 1960s, Harvard University made two hires that would greatly impact the direction of political theory for the next several decades, namely
John Rawls (1962) and Robert Nozick (1969). Prior to their philosophical works in the following decade, political theory in the English-speaking world was dominated by consequentialism or utilitarianism – theories that view justice in terms of the consequences of one’s conduct on happiness, the good, or utility in the world. After their interventions, this was most certainly no longer true; discussions of individuals’ rights, freedom and equality were now centerstage.

The most systematic political thinker of the two was Rawls, and in 1971, he published A Theory of Justice, which aimed to challenge the current state of affairs in political theory and, indeed, revolutionized political theory. Simplified, Rawls proposed that when we think about the most basic questions of justice, like the basic principles of our constitution, to do it well, a certain thought experiment is useful:

Like the blindfolded Lady Justice, imagine that you and your fellow citizens, cloaked in a veil of ignorance and seeking to protect and ensure a set of primary goods that you all need to live well, are discussing the question of which principles should govern your basic public legal and political institutions. The
veil of ignorance makes it impossible for each of you to know facts about yourself that track bias and oppression (such as your class, your sex, your race, your talents and abilities, religion etc.) and also exactly what your conception of the good or happy life is. The set of primary goods, instead, is assumed to include both natural goods like intelligence, imagination, and health and social goods like rights, liberties, income and wealth, and social bases of self-respect that you all want and need to do well regardless of what kind of life you find meaningful. If we deliberate well, under these conditions, Rawls proposed, we will be able to identify principles that should negotiate our interactions in a way that is fair to each citizen viewed as free and equal; hence Rawls calls his position “justice as fairness.”

Rawls proposes that when we deliberate in this space – which he calls “the original position” – we will end up concluding that two principles of justice – the principles of justice as fairness – should ground our public legal and political institutions. The first principle states, simplified, that each person has fundamental, indefeasible rights to an adequate set of basic liberties that is consistent with the same set for each and all. The second principle concerns social and economic inequalities, and it has two parts:

(i) the principle of opportunity, according to which public offices and positions must be open to all; and
(ii) the difference principle, according to which these inequalities can only be justified insofar as they are to the greatest benefit of the least advantaged members of society.

He also proposed that our deep intuitions of justice neither permit us to let considerations of the second principle override the first nor considerations of the difference principle to override those of the principle of opportunity. Rawls, in short, proposed that only societies that are based on these principles, so understood, can justify any claim that the basic structure of their public legal and political institutions is consistent with treating its citizens as free and equal.

Nozick was deeply unconvinced and worried by Rawls’s theory, and just three years later – lightning speed in academia – he published Anarchy, State, and Utopia (1974), which claimed that Rawls’s theory does not secure each person’s freedom and equality through principles of justice as fairness. Nozick argued that Rawls’s justice as fairness is actually a theory that is profoundly unfair on those who work hard and do well; indeed, Nozick thinks, it is a theory that makes freedom impossible and enslavement a reality. Nozick is especially critical of the difference principle. He argued that if we let the difference principle structure our legal and political institutions, then we end up with a society in which individuals do not have equal rights to be free.

Nozick illustrates this logic by invoking the famous American basketball player Wilt Chamberlain. Imagine, he writes, that many people want to come to see Chamberlain play, and they are willing, and thus freely choose to pay money to do so. As a result, Chamberlain becomes quite rich quite fast. The problem, according to Nozick, is that the difference principle is inconsistent with this wealth accumulating to Chamberlain – a wealth that is the result of Chamberlain working hard to realize his talents and the free choices of paying individuals – because the difference principle seemingly requires a transfer of (some of) this wealth from Chamberlain to those who are the least advantaged in society (through taxation). Hence, Nozick argues, Rawls’s theory of justice as fairness is inconsistent with any exercise of liberty because free choices will always upset patterns of economic distribution. Put another way, Rawls’s theory of justice as fairness requires a certain end-result theory of economic justice to be maintained – that economic inequalities always benefit the worst off – but this is inconsistent with liberty because liberty is fundamentally open-ended in terms of end-results. You can’t have it both ways in your theory; you have to choose either freedom or certain end-results. In this way, Nozick’s critique was also that although Rawls wanted to present a theory that is not consequentialist, he in fact ended up with one that is.

From the 1970s, political theory in the English-speaking world was no longer the same: the theories of Rawls and Nozick have since been critically engaged or developed from all theoretical directions. Among the very many works that have utilized the theories of Rawls or Nozick, three especially have been significant in broadening the horizons of the philosophical tradition to encompass feminist philosophy, the philosophy of race, and the philosophy of disability: Susan Okin Moller’s Justice Gender and the Family (1989), Charles Mills The Racial Contract (1997), and Eva Kittay Love’s Labor (1999).

Importantly too, of course, in the United States – where these two thinkers lived – Rawls’s liberalism fit well with the kind of left-leaning political thinking dominant in the Democratic Party in the late 1900s, while Nozick’s libertarianism appeals to the sort of right-wing political thinking found in the Republican Part of the same time period. Hence too, for better or for worse, discussions around these two political thinkers often also channeled much party-political sentiment into these academic discussions in the US.

Finally, these discussions – crucial as they were to igniting post-consequentialist or post-utilitarian political theory in the English-speaking world – are actually rooted in older philosophical discussions. And since scholars around the world are celebrating Immanuel Kant’s 300th birthday this year – with birthday parties, conferences, special publications, and all the other things academics do to celebrate such events – and both Rawls and Nozick viewed themselves as presenting Kant-inspired theories, focusing on this Kant connection seems appropriate.

Most of us know about
Kant indirectly in that his thinking about human dignity, freedom, natural science, and religion has revolutionized our world to that point that when we invoke our “common sense” on these topics, we often (unwittingly) draw on Kant’s ideas. In the 1970s, when Rawls and Nozick were writing and publishing their theories, it was Kant’s works on ethics – especially on freedom and dignity – that inspired most political thinkers, including Rawls and Nozick.

As was common at the time, therefore, Rawls and Nozick didn’t engage with what is now known as Kant’s main legal and political writing, a work called the “Doctrine of Right,” which we find in Kant’s The Metaphysics of Morals. One reason consequentialism was so influential before Rawls and Nozick was correspondingly the peculiar historical fact that this work of Kant had received so little scholarly attention. This, however, changed towards the end of the 1990s and into the 2000s. As Rawls revised and developed his theory of justice as fairness – in books like Political Liberalism (1993) and The Law of Peoples (1993) – Kant scholars now engaged with both Rawls and Nozick by using the critical tools given us by Kant himself in addition to presenting their own, new Kantian theories of justice based on Kant’s “Doctrine of Right.” These new theories were fundamentally grounded in Kant’s works and often claim to keep what is good in Rawls or Nozick and move beyond them – some also with the help of other neglected works (of Kant and others).

To make their case, some Kantians argue that although more philosophically sophisticated than Nozick’s account in many regards and being a more consistent freedom theory, Kant defends a position theoretically very close to the libertarian one Nozick defends. The most influential book of this kind is Sharon B. Byrd and Joachim Hruschka’s Kant’s Doctrine of Right: A Commentary.

Others disagree, arguing in ways that are philosophically much closer to Rawls. For instance, Paul Guyer in Kant on Freedom, Law, and Happiness (2000) argues that Kant’s own position is in fact philosophically very similar to Rawls. Others think this is going too far and argue that though the positions are complementary or philosophically similar in several important regards, Kant’s argument is much more complex than Rawls’s, since Kant gives us important theories we cannot find in Rawls. The most influential book of this kind is Arthur Ripstein’s Force and Freedom: Kant’s Legal and Political Philosophy (2009). For example, Kantians of this stripe (including me) maintain that Kant himself provides a theory of the kinds of liberties all human beings should have – what Rawls’s first principle more vaguely characterizes as an adequate set of liberties – such as freedom of thought and the right to bodily integrity, to private property, to contract, and to start a family. In addition, for these Kantians, Kant gives us philosophical resources that enable us to understand why poverty is a systemic problem that the state (and not private individuals) has the right and duty of justice to assume responsibility for. Kant can explain why the state must ensure that all citizens have legal access to means at all times, including why citizens’ exercise of freedom cannot be made dependent on charity or on someone wanting to hire them. More generally, Kant can explain why the state must assume a monopoly on coercion and responsibility for the economy, the financial system, and legal movement across land.

Not only does Kant have the resources to answer Nozick’s criticisms, but, in my view, he does not appeal to the kinds of arguments Nozick finds objectionable in Rawls. Indeed, some of the ingeniousness of Kant’s theory in the “Doctrine of Right” is that he can show that if you argue consistently from the foundation of each person’s right to freedom – understood as a right not to be enslaved – you cannot end up with Nozick’s libertarianism. Kant’s “Doctrine of Right” can also show us why Nozick’s famous Wilt Chamberlain argument doesn’t get off the ground. In Nozick’s example, Chamberlain’s contract gives him 25 cents per $1 of the entrance fees of those paying to see him play. The problem is that once we introduce money – dollars and cents – and professional basketball teams, it is no longer philosophically plausible only to appeal to what Chamberlain and his fans do. We must now explain how freedom is possible within an economic system on which we are all dependent, one that also requires a financial system enabled by the state through legislation, the issuing and controlling of legal tender (including money), and the positing, applying, and enforcing laws governing businesses (including professional basketball teams). We need an explanation, in other words, of how freedom is possible once our exercise of it is systemically dependent. What we need and what Nozick doesn’t and cannot (given his theoretical parameters) provide (while Kant can) is an account of systemic (in)justice.

Finally, as might be expected from the above, many Kantians have been and are working with philosophical resources found in other neglected Kant texts to help us overcome Kant’s own sexism, racism, heterosexism, ablism, etc., including as we find them in his “Doctrine of Right,” views contrary to his principled theory of justice as freedom. In fact, in my view, some of the most exciting contemporary philosophy – what we might call the “philosophy of the isms” -- is happening exactly here.

To illustrate the spirit of some of this work, consider again Rawls’s veil of ignorance or Nozick’s Chamberlain example. We may reasonably point out that in understanding the complex questions of justice surrounding Chamberlain, we cannot avoid the glaringly obvious fact that Chamberlain was a Black man who lived in the US, where playing professional basketball within the parameters of the NBA was one of the very few opportunities available to young Black men of his generation. Hence, there is something troublesome about choosing an actual Black player (without even noting this fact) and then arguing as if (or that) the most fundamental questions of justice facing this person at this historical time in the US is whether or not he is taxed for his income to benefit the worst off in society. After all, it seems fair to say, one of the most basic problems of justice facing Chamberlain (and any other actual basketball player, however racialized) at this time was the fact of racism (in the US generally and in professional NBA basketball). And this is a question that Nozick never mentions or takes on, since in an ideal, just world – hence as a matter of ideal theory – this problem would not exist and in this world, the biggest danger to freedom would be redistributive taxation measures. The problem is not that Nozick doesn’t have an in principle argument against Rawls; the problem is that these ideal theories of justice seem unable to capture important aspects of actual and particular cases of serious injustice. In a spirit similar to Moller Okin, Mills and Kittay, many so-called non-ideal philosophers of the isms today focus some of their criticism exactly on this type of issue. They emphasize that we don’t live in the ideal world and our theories are not minimally satisfying if they cannot also help us think better about, and act better in our ever so real, messy non-ideal realities.

In addition, notice too that reasoning behind Rawls’s veil of ignorance is insufficient to address the way in which our reasoning is easily skewed and distorted when we live in worlds characterized by systemic forces of racism, sexism, heterosexism, ablism, etc. For example, here we might point to other facts Nozick fails to mention: Chamberlain is also known for his inability to handle important complexities concerning his racialized or gendered identity. Such failures and blind spots are common among those who are able to break glass ceilings, and they are important to understand if we are to adequately characterize the problems of systemic injustice of our times. And neither Rawls’s nor Nozick’s theories can help us there.

Understanding basic questions of justice, including in relation to Chamberlain, then, is much more complicated than reasoning behind the veil of ignorance – which blinds us to phenomena tracking the history of
race and gender – or the question of whether or not the income from his professional basketball games should be taxed so as to assist those who find themselves in the most disadvantaged societal positions. And, some of us argue, that although Kant-the-man wasn’t able to do this, his philosophical system – especially in dialogue with the world of neglected freedom thinkers of the past – gives us resources with which we can theorize these aspects of justice better. Rawls and Nozick were, in other words, crucial to helping us yet again take up and develop further philosophical resources left behind by those who went before us, thereby also honoring their efforts to strive to leave the world a little better, a little freer than we found it.


Helga Varden is a Norwegian-American philosopher and Professor of Philosophy and Gender and Women Studies at the University of Illinois at Urbana-Champaign.

Related Posts:

Rejecting the Anthropocene is a mistake
Nationalism and the Left
Misinformation is the symptom, not the disease
Beyond the Anthropocene: We must rethink our epoch
Freedom from nature: the ultimate enslavement By Slavoj Žižek
Hobbes vs Rousseau: are we inherently evil? By Robin Douglass

Related Videos:

Biology beyond genes
Electricity creates consciousness
The trouble with string theory
The matrix, myths, and metaphysics
Protest, democracy and power With Peter Tatchell

本文於 修改第 1 次
回應 回應給此人 推薦文章 列印 加入我的文摘
引用網址:https://city.udn.com/forum/trackback.jsp?no=2976&aid=7230815
頁/共3頁 回應文章第一頁 回應文章上一頁 回應文章下一頁 回應文章最後一頁