網路城邦
回本城市首頁 時事論壇
市長:胡卜凱  副市長:
加入本城市推薦本城市加入我的最愛訂閱最新文章
udn城市政治社會政治時事【時事論壇】城市/討論區/
討論區知識和議題 字體:
看回應文章  上一個討論主題 回文章列表 下一個討論主題
總體經濟學新論 - C. Niggle
 瀏覽5,169|回應4推薦1

胡卜凱
等級:8
留言加入好友
文章推薦人 (1)

胡卜凱

Evolutionary Keynesianism: A Synthesis of Institutionalist and Post Keynesian Macroeconomics

 

Chris Niggle, Journal of Economic Issues

 

The dominant paradigm in mainstream macroeconomics is a synthesis of new Keynesian and new endogenous growth economics, which has modified the new classical and monetarist-based neoliberal macroeconomics known as the "Washington Consensus." The same model appears dominant in the United Kingdom and perhaps in Euroland's European Central Bank and the EU countries as well. Evolutionary/institutionalist and Post Keynesian economics (IPK) offers a very different approach to policy making which could be characterized as "evolutionary Keynesianism." (1) This paper compares and contrasts the two approaches to macroeconomics. (2)

 

Dominant (or hegemonic) in the mainstream means

 

1. The view of most policy advisors (Federal Reserve, Council of Economic Advisors, IMF, World Bank, Bank of England, European Central Bank).

2. Appearing in the most widely adopted textbooks and taught in the universities.

3. Taught and supported in the elite graduate schools.

4. Accepted by the majority of the profession.

 

The history of macroeconomics over the last fifty years can be interpreted as a dialectical struggle between two opposing visions of the economy (as in Schumpeter's "pre-analytic visions" with which economists begin their work):

 

1. Stable, tending toward short-run equilibrium at the natural rate of unemployment and potential output; tending toward a "steady state" long-run rate of growth determined by the rate of technological change and growth in inputs. Business cycles are caused by external disturbances or supply shocks. The role of the state should be limited to providing the necessary institutional infrastructure, especially property rights, money and competitive markets. This approach originated in classical economics and reappeared in new classical economics (NCE); it also underlies Solovian growth theory (see chaps. 5 and 11 in Snowden and Vane 2005 for good overviews of NCE and Solow-type growth model).

2. Inherently unstable, with unemployment usually greater than optimal, and capacity utilization lower than optimal. The actual growth rate is determined by short-run cycles in production as well as the factors cited in classical, NCE, and Solovian growth theory; the growth rate is usually lower than optimal. Demand is unstable and usually insufficient. Macro policy can improve performance greatly. Marx, Keynes, and institutionalist-Post Keynesian economists share this view of the economy.

3. New Keynesian economics (NKE) emerged in the 1980s; it occupies a third, intermediate position.

 

New Keynesian Economics

 

NKE accepts most of the NCE microeconomic core: flexible wages, prices, and interest rates lead the economy to the "natural rate" of unemployment (usually termed the NAIRU, or "non-accelerating rate of inflation unemployment rate"), which can be described as a Walrasian and Hicksian general equilibrium. But the adjustment process may take a long time due to "coordination failures" caused by inflexible wages and prices. The level of GDP fluctuates around the "potential" GDP, which is produced when unemployment is at the natural rate. Business cycles are temporary deviations from the long-run trend growth rate, caused by supply or demand shocks. The trend growth rate and the natural rate of unemployment are both "strong attractors" dominated by the rate of technological change and the institutional and historical factors which influence labor markets.

 

Large demand gaps can and should be offset by demand management policies, using monetary policy. Fiscal policy is too clumsy a tool because the political and implementation time lags are too long and the multiplier effects of fiscal policy are small. Therefore, fiscal policy is useful only for extreme crises and monetary policy should be used for normal stabilization situations; although "fine tuning" is impossible, "rough tuning" is possible. This represents a modification of the extreme laissez-faire/ nonintervention approach supported by NCE.

 

NKE recognizes the social costs of recessions and the importance of demand factors; it defends countercyclical monetary policy and advocates demand management using "constrained rules" such as (John) Taylor's rule. In most versions, the procedure is to estimate (or forecast) potential GDP and any demand gap and then adjust (nominal and real) interest rates to move actual GDP to its potential; monetary policy should target interest rates rather than the money stock since the velocity of money is unstable and the money supply is endogenous. Fiscal budgets should be balanced over the business cycle. (See Mankiw 1990 and Mankiw and Romer 1991 for descriptions of the NK approach.)

 

The principal contribution of NKE has been to provides microeconomic foundations that explain why wages and prices are sticky in modern economies (imperfect competition, management strategy, menu costs, information costs, contracts, and efficiency wages are often cited) and to model the implications of this market behavior for macroeconomics. NKE rationalizes state intervention to improve short-period macroeconomic performance. Reducing the natural rate of unemployment requires restructuring labor markets (increasing labor market "flexibility").

 

New Endogenous Growth Theory

 

Most NK economists also accept new endogenous growth theory (NEG), which first appeared in the late 1970s/early 1980s (Romer 1994 provides an account of the rise of NEG; see also chapter 11, Snowden and Vane 2005). NEG accepts the NCE/ NKE vision of the natural rate of unemployment and the Solow growth model equilibrium steady state growth rate (the latter determined primarily by technological change) as the normal states which the economy tends toward. NEG also accepts the NCE/ Solow argument that savings finances investment, so that an increase in the savings rate leads to more investment and at least temporarily a higher growth rate. But NEG rejects the NCE/Solow proposition that diminishing marginal returns to capital occurs as the capital/labor (K/L) ratio increases. Increasing returns are possible, so that the growth rate does not necessarily tend toward Solow's rate of technological change, the "steady state" growth rate for per capita real income.

 

Increasing or constant returns to capital are seen as possible due to phenomena such as—

 

1. Effects of R&D, spillover effects, externalities, learning by doing, and the interrelationships between investment in fixed and human capital.

2. Economies of scale and scope across industries, technologies, and economies.

 

NEG implies that—

 

1. Higher saving and investment rates can lead to permanently higher growth rates.

2. Conditional convergence of growth rates for countries with similar savings rates may not occur.

3. Poor countries will not automatically catch up to rich countries, even if they save a lot.

4. There exists a wide range of intelligent policy choices to promote growth, including public investment in fixed capital, human capital, research, and other forms of public infrastructure. Policy promoting high private investment (and saving) rates are growth promoting. Both NK and NEG support state intervention to promote the wealth of nations (full employment and higher growth rates); again, this is quite different from the "free market fundamentalism" and radical laissez-faire of new classical economics.

 

Institutionalist and Post Keynesian Economics: Evolutionary Keynesianism

 

Institutionalist and PK economists tell similar macro stories. The macroeconomics of first and second generation evolutionary or institutionalist economists such as John R. Commons, Thorstein Veblen, and Wesley Mitchell were similar to John Maynard Keynes' in many respects. Many of the recent contributors to institutionalist macroeconomics published in the JEI such as John Cornwall, Paul Davidson, Hyman Minsky, Basil Moore, and Randy Wray also contributed to Post Keynesian economics) Institutionalist and Post Keynesian economists argue that economic development is conditioned by and transforms economic institutions such as money, markets, and property rights: transformational growth leads to structural and institutional change (Nell 1992). Economies should be understood as complex systems with emerging properties that successively develop different laws of motion and pose different problems (Moore 1999). State intervention to create or change institutions is often necessary to promote the goals of full employment, economic growth, equity, social justice, and harmony. Given the emphases on institutional change, full employment, and demand management, "evolutionary Keynesianism or evolutionary macroeconomics" are appropriate terms for the IPK approach and models.

 

There are some similarities between IPK and NKE (the importance of aggregate demand is the chief common element), and IPK accepts much of NEG; there are, however, important distinctions between IPK and the orthodox consensus with respect to ultimate goals, assumptions, method, analysis, and policy.

 

Differences between IPK and NK/NEG

 

1.     IPK--especially PK--emphasizes the importance of "fundamental" or "absolute uncertainty," Paul Davidson's "non-ergodicity," as a characteristic of the real world which has important implications for both theory and policy (2005). NCE and NKE economics both assume "probabilistic risk," which is more tractable but unrealistic.

 

2.     The economy is inherently unstable because of this profound uncertainty--which implies great risk for many crucial decisions-and the resultant instability of expectations regarding profits from investment and the future price of assets. Financial instability and economic instability are dialectically interactive and must be constrained with appropriate institutions. Instability is not as important a concern in NKE economics, and financial markets are discussed largely as an afterthought. Financial markets and money are central to IPK macro (following Keynes' attempt to develop a "monetary theory of production." (See Davidson 2005, Niggle 2004, Rotheim 1998, and Setterfield 2002 for introductions to PK economics and contrasts between IPK and NKE/NEG.)

 

3.     Economies are best understood as "complex systems" which are "self organizing" and exhibit "emerging properties" as they develop-using the insights and language of complexity analysis (Moore 1999). This proposition is a modern version of a core concept in original evolutionary economics: since institutions and economies evolve through historical time, theory must be institutionally specific if it is to be useful. Since the behavior of a complex system is not simply the outcome of the behavior of its components, the complexity proposition also means that we can't adequately understand an economy (a complex system) by observing the behavior of a component and extrapolating that behavior to the system as a whole (as Keynes observed in his "paradox of thrift" argument). Rather than the "microeconomic foundations of macroeconomics" (as in NCE and NKE) we need to understand the "macroeconomic foundations of microeconomics."

 

4.     External shocks and inflexible wages and prices explain recessions and deviations from trend for NKE; IPK argues that even if wages and prices were flexible, full employment is not guaranteed. There is no unique natural rate or NAIRU which the economy gravitates toward and which acts as a strong attractor. IPK argues that flexible wages and prices would enhance instability since falling wages and prices in a recession would probably reduce profits, investment, and employment. Sticky wages, prices, and interest rates are a good thing; institutions which stabilize these are useful and should be developed (national collective bargaining; incomes policy).

 

5.     IPK emphasizes insufficient aggregate demand as a cause for low growth as well as recessions (NKE only recessions). IPK advocates demand-enhancing policy, including inequality-educing tax, transfer and expenditure systems, low interest rates, and employer of last resort programs. Most IPK economists favor Lerner's "functional finance" theory of fiscal policy: the levels of taxation and government expenditure should be consistent with full employment and price stability (Nell and Forstater 2003).

 

6.     Money is not neutral: changes in the price and availability of liquidity have powerful effects on the real economy; macroeconomics should begin with an analysis of the roles of liquidity in the economy, as in Keynes' "monetary theory of production." But IPK economists are skeptical regarding the power of monetary policy by itself and see fiscal policy as a more powerful tool for demand management. They are skeptical re "rules," in favor of "discretion" in policy.

 

7.     IPK follows Keynes and Kalecki in arguing that savings do not finance or determine investment. Profit expectations, interest rates, and the availability and the cost of finance are the important influences on investment--not the flow of savings-since the former variables are largely independent of saving. Savings are determined by the level of income, itself determined by aggregate demand. The NK/NEG argument that policy should encourage higher saving is generally incorrect: high saving can mean low aggregate demand, capacity utilization, and investment.

 

8.     IPK puts a higher priority on full employment than on low inflation; full employment is understood as the rate of unemployment that obtains when everyone who desires employment and is willing to work at the going wage rate for workers with comparable skills is employed. Inflation is seen as the result of distributional struggles between capital and labor which can lead to "cost push" inflation. Again, institutions which socially control wages, prices, and the distribution of income are necessary for full employment and price stability--some form of incomes policy. Many (but not all) IPK economists argue for government employer of last resort programs as necessary for full employment (Wray 1998).

 

9.     IPK sees a strong reinforcing link between demand, cycles, and growth: high demand leads to high employment and capacity utilization, which leads to high investment, which leads to higher productivity in the next period (higher growth).

 

10. The distribution of income influences aggregate demand. More equality is demand, investment, profit, and growth enhancing.

 

11. IPK proposes "demand-led" growth economics; propositions 7, 8, 9, and 10 are not in NKE/NEG; IPK is richer and has more explanatory power and more usefulness in informing the design of macro policy. (See the essays in Cornwall and Cornwall 2001, Setterfield 2002, and Nell 1992.)

 

12. Most IPK economists favor some form of exchange rate regime which would reduce exchange rate instability; most NKE economists accept flexible ER systems (Davidson 2002).

 

13. IPK economists favor financial market regulation and see unregulated markets as instability enhancing (Isenberg 2000); most NK economists see financial instability and crises as occasional episodes which can be handled on an ad hoc basis.

 

What Do Economists Actually Believe about Macroeconomics?

 

Most macroeconomic textbooks and surveys of modern macroeconomics such as Brian Snowden and Howard R. Vane's Modern Macroeconomics (2005, chapter 12) argue that there is an emerging consensus among macroeconomists based upon a new Keynesian-new economic growth theory model. On the other hand, IPK economists argue against the validity of this consensus (for example, Arestis and Sawyer 2004, Nell and Forstater 2003, Lavoie and Seccareccia 2005, and the contributors to the JPKE Symposium cited in note 1).

 

Dan Fuller and Doris Geide-Stevenson (2003) surveyed a random sample of 1,000 AEA members; they report "fluidity" and not much consensus regarding macroeconomics among the (298) respondents to their survey. The reported views on eighteen macro propositions indicate as much support for propositions consistent with IPK as for NKE or NCE propositions, suggesting that IPK views are fairly widely accepted and that they might become more widely accepted in future.

 

Sources

 

Arestis, Philip, and Malcolm Sawyer. Neoliberal Economic Policy. Cheltenham, U.K., and Northampton, Mass.: Edward Elgar, 2004.

Arestis, Philip, M. Baddeley, and J. McCombie, eds. The New Monetary Policy. Cheltenham, U.K., and Northampton, Mass.: Edward Elgar, 2006.

Atkinson, Glen, and Theodore Oleson. "Keynes and Commons: Their Attack on Laissez-Faire." Journal of Economic Issues 32 (1998): 1019-1030.

Cornwall, John, and Wendy Cornwall. Capitalist Development in the Twentieth Century: An Evolutionary Keynesian Analysis. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2001.

Davidson, Paul. Financial Markets, Money, and the Real World. Northampton, Mass.: Edward Elgar, 2002.

--. "The Post Keynesian School." In Modern Macroeconomics, edited by Brian Snowden and Howard Vane. Cheltenham, U.K., and Northampton, Mass.: Edward Elgar, 2005.

Federal Reserve Bank of Kansas City. Symposium: Rethinking Stabilization Policy, 2002.

Fuller, Dan, and Doris Geide-Stevenson. "Consensus among Economists Revisited." Journal of Economic Education (Fall 2003): 369-87.

Hodgson, Geoff. "Post-Keynesianism and Institutionalism: Another Look at the Link." In Setterfield 1999.

Isenberg, Dorene. "The Political Economy of Financial Reform." In Capitalism, Socialism and Radical Political Economy, edited by Robert Pollin. Northampton, Mass.: Edward Elgar, 2000.

Lavoie, Marc, and Mario Seccareccia, eds. Central Banking in the Modern World. Cheltenham, U.K., and Northampton, Mass.:Edward Elgar, 2005.

Mankiw, N. Gregory. "A Quick Refresher Course in Macroeconomics." Journal of Economic Literature 28 (December 1990): 1645-1660.

Mankiw, N. Gregory, and David Romer, eds. New Keynesian Economics. Cambridge: MIT Press. 1991.

Ann-Marie Meulendyke. U.S. Monetary Policy and Financial Markets. Federal Reserve Bank of New York, 1998.

Moore, Basil. "Economics and Complexity." In Growth, Employment, and Inflation, edited by Mark Setterfield. New York: St. Martin's and Macmillan, 1999.

Nell, Edward. Transformational Growth and Effective Demand. New York: New York University Press, 1992.

Nell, Edward, and Matthew Forstater, eds. Reinventing Functional Finance: Transformational Growth and Employment. Cheltenham, U.K., and Northampton, Mass.: Edward Elgar, 2003.

Niggle, Christopher. "A Short Course in Macroeconomics or Whatever Happened to Monetarism?" Unpublished, University of Redlands, California, 2004. http://www.redlands.edu/christopher_niggle/xml.

Romer, Christina, and David Romer. "The Evolution of Economic Understanding and Postwar Stabilization Policy." In Rethinking Stabilization Policy, FRB, KC, 2002.

Romer, Paul. "The Origins of Endogenous Growth." Journal of Economic Perspectives (Winter 1994).

Rotheim, Roy, ed. New Keynesian Economics/Post Keynesian Alternatives. London and New York: Routledge, 1998.

Setterfield, Mark, ed. Growth, Employment, and Inflation. New York: St. Martin's and Macmillan, 1999.

--. The Economics of Demand-Led Growth. Cheltenham, U.K., and Northampton, Mass.: Edward Elgar, 2002.

Snowdon, Brian, and Howard Vane. "Conclusions and Reflections." Chapter 12 of Modern Macroeconomics, edited by Brian Snowdon and Howard Vane. Cheltenham, U.K., and Northampton, Mass.: Edward Elgar, 2005.

Tymoigne, Eric. "Keynes and Commons on Money." Journal of Economic Issues 37, no. 3 (September 2003): 527-45.

Wray, L. Randall. Understanding Modern Money. Cheltenham, U.K., and Northampton, Mass.: Edward Elgar, 1998.

 

Notes

 

(1.) For discussions of the emerging new Keynesian-new economic growth theory consensus, see the symposium on monetary policy in the Journal of Post Keynesian Economics, Summer 2002 (articles by Philip Arestis and Malcolm Sawyer, Victoria Chick and Sheila Dow, Paul Dalziel, Giuseppe Fontana, Giuseppa Fontana and Alfonso Palacio-Vera, Iris Beifang-Frisanco Mariscal, and Peter Howells); Federal Reserve Bank of Kansas City, Symposium: Rethinking Stabilization Policy 2002 (especially "The Evolution of Economic Understanding and Postwar Stabilization Policy" by C. Romer and D. Romer); Arestis and Sawyer 2004; Arestis, Baddeley, and McCombie 2006; Lavoie and Seccareccia 2005; Mulendyke 1998; Snowden and Vane 2005 (especially chap. 12, "Conclusions and Reflections"). John and Wendy Cornwall (2001) proposed the term "evolutionary Keynesianism" for their synthesis of institutionalism and post Keynesian macroeconomics; it appears to be an appropriate term for the IPK approach.

(2.) For an extended version of this paper see Niggle 2004, which presents a brief narrative of the history of macroeconomics since WWII as well as comparison and contrasts between the various schools of thought during this period.

(3.) See Atkinson and Oleson 1998, Hodgson 1999, and Tymoigne 2003 for discussions of the institutionalist-PK connection.

 

The author is Professor of Economics at University of Redlands, California. This paper was presented at the annual meeting of the Association for Evolutionary Economics in Boston January 6-8, 2006.

 

Publication information: Article title: Evolutionary Keynesianism: A Synthesis of Institutionalist and Post Keynesian Macroeconomics. Contributors: Niggle, Chris - Author. Journal title: Journal of Economic Issues. Volume: 40. Issue: 2 Publication date: June 2006. Page number: 405+. © 1999 Association for Evolutionary Economics. COPYRIGHT 2006 Gale Group.

 

This material is protected by copyright and, with the exception of fair use, may not be further copied, distributed or transmitted in any form or by any means.

 

http://www.questia.com/read/1G1-147218418/evolutionary-keynesianism-a-synthesis-of-institutionalist



本文於 修改第 2 次
回應 回應給此人 推薦文章 列印 加入我的文摘

引用
引用網址:https://city.udn.com/forum/trackback.jsp?no=2976&aid=4893508
 回應文章
行為經濟學與公共政策的制定 - T. Harford
推薦1


胡卜凱
等級:8
留言加入好友

 
文章推薦人 (1)

胡卜凱

Behavioural economics and public policy

 

Tim Harford, 03/21/14

 

The past decade has been a triumph for behavioural economics, the fashionable cross-breed of psychology and economics. First there was the award in 2002 of the Nobel Memorial Prize in economics to a psychologist, Daniel Kahneman – the man who did as much as anything to create the field of behavioural economics. Bestselling books were launched, most notably by Kahneman himself (Thinking, Fast and Slow , 2011) and by his friend Richard Thaler, co-author of Nudge (2008). Behavioural economics seems far sexier than the ordinary sort, too: when last year’s Nobel was shared three ways, it was the behavioural economist Robert Shiller who grabbed all the headlines.

 

Behavioural economics is one of the hottest ideas in public policy. The UK government’s Behavioural Insights Team (BIT) uses the discipline to craft better policies, and in February was part-privatised with a mission to advise governments around the world. The White House announced its own behavioural insights team last summer.

 

So popular is the field that behavioural economics is now often misapplied as a catch-all term to refer to almost anything that’s cool in popular social science, from the storycraft of Malcolm Gladwell, author of The Tipping Point (2000), to the empirical investigations of Steven Levitt, co-author of Freakonomics (2005).

 

Yet, as with any success story, the backlash has begun. Critics argue that the field is overhyped, trivial, unreliable, a smokescreen for bad policy, an intellectual dead-end – or possibly all of the above. Is behavioural economics doomed to reflect the limitations of its intellectual parents, psychology and economics? Or can it build on their strengths and offer a powerful set of tools for policy makers and academics alike?

 

A recent experiment designed by BIT highlights both the opportunity and the limitations of the new discipline. The trial was designed to encourage people to sign up for the Organ Donor Register. It was huge; more than a million people using the Driver and Vehicle Licensing Agency website were shown a webpage inviting them to become an organ donor. One of eight different messages was displayed at random. One was minimalist, another spoke of the number of people who die while awaiting donations, yet another appealed to the idea of reciprocity – if you needed an organ, wouldn’t you want someone to donate an organ to you?

 

BIT devoted particular attention to an idea called “social proof”, made famous 30 years ago by psychologist Robert Cialdini’s book Influence. While one might be tempted to say, “Too few people are donating their organs, we desperately need your help to change that”, the theory of social proof says that’s precisely the wrong thing to do. Instead, the persuasive message will suggest: “Every day, thousands of people sign up to be donors, please join them.” Social proof describes our tendency to run with the herd; why else are books marketed as “bestsellers”?

 

Expecting social proof to be effective, the BIT trial used three different variants of a social proof message, one with a logo, one with a photo of smiling people, and one unadorned. None of these approaches was as successful as the best alternatives at persuading people to sign up as donors. The message with the photograph – for which the teams had high hopes – was a flop, proving worse than no attempt at persuasion at all.

 

Three points should be made here. The first is that this is exactly why running trials is an excellent idea: had the rival approaches not been tested with an experiment, it would have been easy for well-meaning civil servants acting on authoritative advice to have done serious harm. The trial was inexpensive, and now that the most persuasive message is in use (“If you needed an organ transplant, would you have one? If so, please help others”), roughly 100,000 additional people can be expected to sign up for the donor register each year.

 

The second point is that there is something unnerving about a discipline in which our discoveries about the past do not easily generalise to the future. Social proof is a widely accepted idea in psychology but, as the donor experiment shows, it does not always apply and it can be hard to predict when or why.

 

This patchwork of sometimes-fragile psychological results hardly invalidates the whole field but complicates the business of making practical policy. There is a sense that behavioural economics is just regular economics plus common sense – but since psychology isn’t mere common sense either, applying psychological lessons to economics is not a simple task.

 

The third point is that the organ donor experiment has little or nothing to do with behavioural economics, strictly defined. “The Behavioural Insights Team is widely perceived as doing behavioural economics,” says Daniel Kahneman. “They are actually doing social psychology.”

 

The line between behavioural economics and psychology can get a little blurred. Behavioural economics is based on the traditional “neoclassical” model of human behaviour used by economists. This essentially mathematical model says human decisions can usefully be modelled as though our choices were the outcome of solving differential equations. Add psychology into the mix – for example, Kahneman’s insight (with the late Amos Tversky) that we treat the possibility of a loss differently from the way we treat the possibility of a gain – and the task of the behavioural economist is to incorporate such ideas without losing the mathematically-solvable nature of the model.

 

Why bother with the maths? Consider the example of, say, improving energy efficiency. A psychologist might point out that consumers are impatient, poorly-informed and easily swayed by what their neighbours are doing. It’s the job of the behavioural economist to work out how energy markets might work under such conditions, and what effects we might expect if we introduced policies such as a tax on domestic heating or a subsidy for insulation.

 

It’s this desire to throw out the hyper-rational bathwater yet keep the mathematically tractable baby that leads to difficult compromises, and not everyone is happy. Economic traditionalists argue that behavioural economics is now hopelessly patched-together; some psychologists claim it’s still attempting to be too systematic.

 

Nick Chater, a psychologist at Warwick Business School and an adviser to the BIT, is a sympathetic critic of the behavioural economics approach. “The brain is the most rational thing in the universe”, he says, “but the way it solves problems is ad hoc and very local.” That suggests that attempts to formulate general laws of human behaviour may never be more than a rough guide to policy.

 

This shift to radical incrementalism is so much more important than some of the grand proposals out there

 

The most well-known critique of behavioural economics comes from a psychologist, Gerd Gigerenzer of the Max Planck Institute for Human Development. Gigerenzer argues that it is pointless to keep adding frills to a mathematical account of human behaviour that, in the end, has nothing to do with real cognitive processes.

 

I put this critique to David Laibson, a behavioural economist at Harvard University. He concedes that Gigerenzer has a point but adds:

 

“Gerd’s models of heuristic decision-making are great in the specific domains for which they are designed but they are not general models of behaviour.”

 

In other words, you’re not going to be able to use them to figure out how people should, or do, budget for Christmas or nurse their credit card limit through a spell of joblessness.

 

Richard Thaler of the University of Chicago, who with Kahneman and Tversky is the founding father of behavioural economics, agrees. To discard the basic neoclassical framework of economics means “throwing away a lot of stuff that’s useful”.

 

For some economists, though, behavioural economics has already conceded too much to the patchwork of psychology. David K Levine, an economist at Washington University in St Louis, and author of Is Behavioral Economics Doomed? (2012), says: “There is a tendency to propose some new theory to explain each new fact. The world doesn’t need a thousand different theories to explain a thousand different facts. At some point there needs to be a discipline of trying to explain many facts with one theory.

 

The challenge for behavioural economics is to elaborate on the neoclassical model to deliver psychological realism without collapsing into a mess of special cases. Some say that the most successful special case comes from Harvard’s David Laibson. It is a mathematical tweak designed to represent the particular brand of short-termism that leads us to sign up for the gym yet somehow never quite get around to exercising. It’s called “hyperbolic discounting”, a name that refers to a mathematical curve, and which says much about the way behavioural economists represent human psychology.

 

The question is, how many special cases can behavioural economics sustain before it becomes arbitrary and unwieldy? Not more than one or two at a time, says Kahneman.

 

“You might be able to do it with two but certainly not with many factors.”

 

Like Kahneman, Thaler believes that a small number of made-for-purpose behavioural economics models have proved their worth already. He argues that trying to unify every psychological idea in a single model is pointless.

 

“I’ve always said that if you want one unifying theory of economic behaviour, you won’t do better than the neoclassical model, which is not particularly good at describing actual decision making.”

 

Meanwhile, the policy wonks plug away at the rather different challenge of running rigorous experiments with public policy. There is something faintly unsatisfying about how these policy trials have often confirmed what should have been obvious. One trial, for example, showed that text message reminders increase the proportion of people who pay legal fines. This saves everyone the trouble of calling in the bailiffs. Other trials have shown that clearly-written letters with bullet-point summaries provoke higher response rates.

 

None of this requires the sophistication of a mathematical model of hyperbolic discounting or loss aversion. It is obvious stuff. Unfortunately it is obvious stuff that is often neglected by the civil service. It is hard to object to inexpensive trials that demonstrate a better way. Nick Chater calls the idea “a complete no-brainer”, while Kahneman says “you can get modest gains at essentially zero cost”.

 

David Halpern, a Downing Street adviser under Tony Blair, was appointed by the UK coalition government in 2010 to establish the BIT. He says that the idea of running randomised trials in government has now picked up steam. The Financial Conduct Authority has also used randomisation to develop more effective letters to people who may have been missold financial products. “This shift to radical incrementalism is so much more important than some of the grand proposals out there,” says Halpern.

 

Not everyone agrees. In 2010, behavioural economists George Loewenstein and Peter Ubel wrote in The New York Times that “behavioural economics is being used as a political expedient, allowing policy makers to avoid painful but more effective solutions rooted in traditional economics.”

 

For example, in May 2010, just before David Cameron came to power, he sang the praises of behavioural economics in a TED talk. “The best way to get someone to cut their electricity bill,” he said, “is to show them their own spending, to show them what their neighbours are spending, and then show what an energy-conscious neighbour is spending.”

 

But Cameron was mistaken. The single best way to promote energy efficiency is, almost certainly, to raise the price of energy. A carbon tax would be even better, because it not only encourages people to save energy but to switch to lower-carbon sources of energy. The appeal of a behavioural approach is not that it is more effective but that it is less unpopular.

 

Thaler points to the experience of Cass Sunstein, his Nudge co-author, who spent four years as regulatory tsar in the Obama White House. “Cass wanted a tax on petrol but he couldn’t get one, so he pushed for higher fuel economy standards. We all know that’s not as efficient as raising the tax on petrol – but that would be lucky to get a single positive vote in Congress.”

 

Should we be trying for something more ambitious than behavioural economics? “I don’t know if we know enough yet to be more ambitious,” says Kahneman, “But the knowledge that currently exists in psychology is being put to very good use.”

 

Small steps have taken behavioural economics a long way, says Laibson, citing savings policy in the US. “Every dimension of that environment is now behaviourally tweaked.” The UK has followed suit, with the new auto-enrolment pensions, directly inspired by Thaler’s work.

 

Laibson says behavioural economics has only just begun to extend its influence over public policy. “The glass is only five per cent full but there’s no reason to believe the glass isn’t going to completely fill up.”

 

Tim Harford’s ‘Undercover Economist’ column appears each week at ft.com/harford

本文於 修改第 1 次
回應 回應給此人 推薦文章 列印 加入我的文摘
引用網址:https://city.udn.com/forum/trackback.jsp?no=2976&aid=5069648
評韋伯的「『新教倫理觀」』與『資本主義精神』相關論」 - S. Gregg
推薦1


胡卜凱
等級:8
留言加入好友

 
文章推薦人 (1)

胡卜凱

Why Max Weber Was Wrong          

 

The association of Protestantism with capitalism, famously articulated by Max Weber and now widely accepted by many, is theologically dubious, empirically disprovable, and largely incidental. An edited excerpt from Gregg's new book, Tea Party Catholic.      

 

Samuel Gregg, 12/11/13

 

Max Weber is justly famous for many things, but especially for having developed a theory about the relationship between capitalism and religion. The influence of The Protestant Ethic and the Spirit of Capitalism remains considerable, not least because it has become a staple of sociological literature on the subject.

 

Based on lectures he gave during a visit to America in 1904, Weber’s Protestant Ethic maintained that capitalism’s nature had to be understood as more than just producing and exchanging goods in a particular way (e.g., free exchange) within a particular institutional setting (limited government, etc.). At its heart, Weber insisted, capitalism was a state of mind: an outlook that involved, among other things, the subordination of emotion, custom, tradition, folklore, and myth to the workings of instrumental reason.

 

The real controversy begins with Weber’s argument that the decisive linkage of this form of rationality with economic practices occurred primarily in Europe’s predominantly Protestant areas. He was particularly thinking of countries such as England and the Netherlands, which were home to large numbers of Puritans and Calvinists, many of whom migrated to North America in the seventeenth century. These forms of Protestantism, Weber posited, ingrained the belief among their adherents that they should avoid superficial hobbies, games, and entertainment. Instead, Christians should commit themselves totally to whatever calling to which God had summoned them. Weber believed that these forms of Protestantism, especially their central doctrine of predestination, helped to foster the type of focused minds and disciplined work habits that are essential for market economies.

 

According to Weber, these ascetic Protestants didn’t believe it was possible to do good works to attain heaven in the next world. Either you were among the elect, or you weren’t. Weber interpreted Calvin as suggesting that one indication of election was the acquisition of wealth. It followed -- or so Weber’s theory went -- that the accumulation of wealth encouraged people to see themselves as destined to be saved. This, in turn, fostered a spirit that encouraged believers to grow ever-greater amounts of wealth.

 

On the surface, Weber’s proposition makes considerable sense. After all, many culturally Catholic countries such as Portugal and Spain -- not to mention almost all Latin American nations -- have lagged behind other Western nations in terms of economic development. More careful analysis of Weber’s claims, however, soon reveals them as less-than-adequate.

 

The accuracy, for instance, of Weber’s interpretation of Calvinist theology is open to question. The Westminster Confession -- the profession of faith that dominated Calvinist and Presbyterian theology from the sixteenth century onward, and on which Weber drew in developing his ideas -- indicates that the notion of “calling” in Puritan and Calvinist thinking is difficult to reconcile with the meaning given to it by Weber. The Confession clearly distinguishes between each person’s worldly vocation and his ultimate calling. Moreover, the earthly calling of each individual is not considered to constitute a positive or negative contribution to that person’s salvation.

 

The Westminster Confession also stresses that believers must ensure that their earthly vocation does not distract them from pursuing their heavenly calling. Weber, by contrast, seems to conflate the two. And on the subject of vocation itself, the Confession insists that Christians follow that calling in which they would be most serviceable to God rather than that which brought them “the most honor” in the world. Nothing in the text suggests any particular emphasis on commerce, let alone the idea that acquiring material wealth was somehow a sign of being among the elect.

 

Second, the empirical evidence disproving Weber’s connection between Protestantism and the emergence of capitalism is considerable. Even Catholic critics of modern capitalism have had to concede that “the commercial spiritpreceded the Reformation by at least two hundred years. From the eleventh century onward, the words Deus enim et proficuum (“For God and Profit”) began to appear in the ledgers of Italian and Flemish merchants. This was not a medieval version of some type of prosperity gospel. Rather, it symbolized just how naturally intertwined were the realms of faith and commerce throughout the world of medieval Europe. The pursuit of profit, trade, and commercial success dominated the life of the city-states of medieval and Renaissance Northern Italy and the towns of Flanders, not to mention the Venetian republic that exerted tremendous influence on merchant activity throughout the Mediterranean long before 1517.

 

Since Weber’s time, much scholarly work has been done to illustrate the advanced state of market-driven economic development in the Middle Ages. Throughout the 1940s and 1950s, the Belgian scholar Raymond de Roover penned numerous articles illustrating that, during the Middle Ages, financial transactions and banking started to take on the degree of sophistication that is commonplace today. Likewise, The Commercial Revolution of the Middle Ages, by the Italian-American historian of medieval European economic history, the late Robert S. Lopez, shattered the historical claims that formed much of the background of Weber’s argument. Lopez demonstrated in great detail the way in which the Middle Ages “created the indispensable material and moral conditions for a thousand years of virtually uninterrupted growth.”

 

In recent decades, the historians Edwin Hunt and James Murray have illustrated just how much the medieval period was characterized by remarkable innovation in methods of business organization. They also suggest that the advent of modernity actually heralded the expansion of state economic intervention and regulation in an effort to constrain economic freedom. In a similar fashion, the sociologist Rodney Stark has gathered together disparate sources of historical and economic analysis to illustrate the origins of capitalism and major breakthroughs in the theory and practice of wealth creation in the medieval period. Central to Stark’s analysis is his highlighting of the way pre-Reformation Western Christianity saw the world as one in which humans were called upon to use their reason and innate creativity to develop its resources -- including economically.

 

Here one could add that, before Adam Smith, some of the most elaborate thinking about the nature of contracts, free markets, interest, wages, and banking that developed after the Reformation was articulated in the writings of Spanish Catholic scholastic thinkers of the sixteenth and seventeenth centuries. Theologians such as Francisco de Vitoria OP, Martín de Azpilcueta, Juan de Mariana SJ, and Tomás de Mercado OP, anticipated many of the claims made by Smith two centuries later.

 

To be sure, much of this thinking occurred by way of side-effect rather than as a result of the systematic analysis undertaken by Smith. For as commercial relationships expanded throughout Europe in the centuries preceding and following the Reformation, there was a marked increase in the number of penitents asking their confessors for guidance about moral questions with a strong economic dimension.

 

What was the just price?

When was a person no longer obliged to adhere to a contract?

When was charging interest legitimate?

When did it become usurious?

 

As a result, priests looked to theologians for guidance on how to respond to their penitents’ questions. Thus, as Jürg Niehans stressed in his History of Economic Theory:

 

The scholastics thus found it necessary to descend from theology into the everyday world of economic reality, of early capitalism, foreign trade, monopoly, banking, foreign exchange and public finance. What one knew about these things in the School of Salamanca was hardly less than Adam Smith knew two hundred years later, and more than most students know today.

 

Even when we consider modern capitalism’s emergence, a direct connection between this event and Protestantism is very open to question. The economic historian Jacques Delacroix, for instance, has highlighted many facts about this period that Weber’s theory simply cannot account for. “Amsterdam’s wealth,” Delacroix writes, “was centered on Catholic families; the economically advanced German Rhineland is more Catholic than Protestant; all-Catholic Belgium was the second country to industrialize, ahead of a good half-dozen Protestant entities.”

 

A better explanation for why some parts of Europe lagged behind others is to be found in the influence of absolutism and mercantilism. To our ears, “absolutism” is a word that contains echoes of despotic government. Yet the age of absolutism, which lasted throughout most of Europe from about 1600 until 1800, was a rather different phenomenon. Drawing heavily on the Divine Right of Kings (a theological doctrine always disputed by the Catholic Church) for legitimacy, absolutism was also associated with the rise of the nation-state that began before the Reformation, but which accelerated after 1517.

 

Absolutism’s underlying motif was the conviction that centralizing state power was the path to stronger and wealthier societies. In terms of commercial life, absolutism manifested itself in countries such as Lutheran Prussia, Catholic France, and Orthodox Russia in the form of ever-increasing restrictions on economic freedom. Governments began assuming more top-down direction of economic activity through subsidizing exports, imposing tariffs on imports, and mandating government monopolies of particular trade or products that were then sold or leased to groups of merchants. Adam Smith famously called this set of economic arrangements the mercantile system.

 

It is difficult to downplay mercantilism’s effect on modern economic development. From the Age of Discovery to the late nineteenth century (and in many cases beyond), Catholic Latin America was largely dominated by an absolutist, mercantilist economic culture. Therein, Stark contends, lie some of the fundamental causes of Latin America’s slower economic development as compared to the United States. Even the dominant eighteenth-century Protestant power, Britain, engaged in mercantilist economic practices despite having rejected a drift toward absolutism in the previous century. And as every student of the American Revolution knows, Britain’s mercantilist economic policies contributed mightily to the outbreak of the War of Independence.

 

Much more could be said about these historical observations. The point, however, is that the widespread association of one form of Protestantism with capitalism is theologically dubious, empirically disprovable, and largely incidental. To make these observations is not to propose that modern capitalism was somehow constructed upon a “Catholic ethic.” That would be equally false. It is simply to note that much of Weber’s particular analysis is very questionable and that this should be acknowledged by economists, historians, and above all, by Catholics. How ironic it would be if the last people to believe in Weber’s Protestant ethic thesis were Catholics!

 

Samuel Gregg is Research Director at the Acton Institute. He has authored several books, including Becoming Europe: Economic Decline, Culture, and How America Can Avoid a European Future and most recently Tea Party Catholic: The Catholic Case for Limited Government, a Free Economy, and Human Flourishing.

 

http://www.thepublicdiscourse.com/2013/12/11099/

 

請參考本欄J. Bowyer 教授大作宗教是經濟成長的主要動力之一?(Is Religion An Essential Driver Of Economic Growth?, 06/09/13)以及我的一篇回應宗教和經濟成長真的相關?Gregg教授可說簡明扼要的批駁了韋伯「新教倫理觀」孕育或助長「資本主義精神」的觀點 -- 卜凱



本文於 修改第 1 次
回應 回應給此人 推薦文章 列印 加入我的文摘
引用網址:https://city.udn.com/forum/trackback.jsp?no=2976&aid=5037007
宗教和經濟成長真的相關?
推薦0


胡卜凱
等級:8
留言加入好友

 

「社會學」以及「知識社會學」和「社會建構論」上,我頗受韋伯和柏格的影響。但我對這篇報導中兩者對「宗教」和「經濟成長」相關的看法並不以為然。此處略表己見,以後有機會再申論。



本文於 修改第 2 次
回應 回應給此人 推薦文章 列印 加入我的文摘
引用網址:https://city.udn.com/forum/trackback.jsp?no=2976&aid=4972099
宗教是經濟成長的主要動力之一? - J. Bowyer
推薦0


胡卜凱
等級:8
留言加入好友

 

Is Religion An Essential Driver Of Economic Growth?

 

Jerry Bowyer, 05/29/13

 

Peter Berger is perhaps the world’s most prominent living sociologist. He has written two dozen books including seminal texts in the development of the sociology of religion, the sociology of knowledge, and the sociology of modern development. He may be the most qualified person to speak with authority on matters pertaining to the relationship between religious beliefs and economic development, so I decided to ask him to explain this to me.  This interview is the result, and it’s worth listening to in full. At age 84 Berger is still sharp as a tack and has a long lifetime of study and analysis behind him (and I expect quite a number ahead of him).

 

When I asked him what he has learned in a lifetime of studying these questions, he told me that there are certain social preconditions to economic development, and that the way a society operates is important in regards to how prosperous that society can become. This is largely a matter of culture, and for most of the world culture basically means religion. Religion drives culture; culture drives social forms; social forms drive development.

 

Regarding different religions and their level of conduciveness to growth, he said that they are not equally conducive. He pointed out the work of Max Weber, whose seminal work, The Protestant Ethic and the Spirit of Capitalism, argued that the lifestyle which arose from Protestantism played a decisive role in the creation of modern prosperity. For Weber, and Berger agrees, the Calvinistic lifestyle of worldly asceticism became a source of growth and capital accumulation. Worldly asceticism (Weber’s phrase) upheld the virtue of productive labor in this world, as opposed to an otherworldly orientation often associated with medieval Catholicism. The focus on this life as opposed to the afterlife tends to create large income streams. But worldly asceticism looks askance at lives of excessive spending and conspicuous consumption, which are often associated with wealth. The result is a well-educated, highly skilled diligent work force and large pools of capital. Without this, or something like it, modern capitalism would not have arisen as it did.

 

Not all religions, at least in the current form, have these same characteristics, therefore not all religions are equally conducive to development. Not surprisingly, Berger says he has been accused of racism or bias because of these views. But he points out that it’s not a matter of bias; it’s simply a matter of facing the facts.

 

According to him, this Protestant effect expressed itself in different ways in different times and places: historically in America in her Puritan heritage. Currently in the developing world, it reveals itself in the explosive growth of Evangelicalism which is helping to create modern developed economies. Perhaps Pentecostalism plays a role in the Third World similar to that played by Calvinism in Europe and North America, or at least is an important factor in the emergence of a middle class.

 

There is an important caveat in all this: Religions change over time and so it’s not helpful to do this sort of analysis in terms of the characteristics of a religion in general, but instead in a certain historical context. For example, Christianity in the Middle Ages may well have retarded economic progress through its embrace of usury laws (which I would argue it got from Aristotle rather than from Christ.)

 

Another caveat urges us to avoid confusing the effects of a religion on institutions with its effects on individuals. According to Berger, Confucianism preaches many of the virtues, such as education, hard work and delayed gratification, which are conducive to prosperity among individuals, but that Confucian disdain for commerce has tended to create societies which are more conducive to entrepreneurial stagnation. Therefore a Confucian China can stagnate for millennia. But when Chinese people migrate to more open societies in Southeast Asia, they become the wealthy ‘overseas Chinese,’ Jews of the East, prospering and helping to prosper the societies they live in, part of the vanguard of economic development. Groups like the overseas Chinese become easy scapegoats for demagogues.

 

Regarding Islam, Berger does not discount the possibility that it might be able to coexist with liberty and prosperity, but points out that historically the subservient role of women in Muslim nations is a source of economic drag. To isolate half of the talent of a population from productive activity is bad enough. But to add to that a pattern of leaving women uneducated makes things even worse because of the role that mothers play in the intellectual development of children. He points to Turkey as a beacon of hope. I am less optimistic than Berger about the much vaunted ‘Turkish model,’ but time will tell.

 

Islamic economics is a subject unto itself and deserves at least one future column of its own. But in case you’re not quite ready for that topic yet, I’d suggest that you listen to my interview with Peter Berger.  Because when it comes to talking about religious differences, there is a policeman in your head who twirls his night stick every time you question the current dictates of our pervasive political correctness speech code, and Peter Berger might help you put that policeman into a helpful retirement.

 

http://www.forbes.com/sites/jerrybowyer/2013/05/29/is-religion-an-essential-driver-of-economic-growth/



本文於 修改第 2 次
回應 回應給此人 推薦文章 列印 加入我的文摘
引用網址:https://city.udn.com/forum/trackback.jsp?no=2976&aid=4972089